1 / 15

Electoral agency in the lab

Electoral agency in the lab. Leif Helland & Lars Monkerud NSM BI. Motivation. Liberal concept of democracy Roots in liberal political philosophy (Mill, Locke)

bin
Télécharger la présentation

Electoral agency in the lab

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Electoral agency in the lab Leif Helland & Lars Monkerud NSM BI

  2. Motivation • Liberal concept of democracy • Roots in liberal political philosophy (Mill, Locke) • Democracy negatively defined: citizens should be free from restraint and exploitation by state power: a) constitutional constraints, b) accountable leadership • Accountability: achieved by retrospective voting for competing alternatives (Schumpeter 1942; Popper 1982, Riker 1984). • A contemporary economists formulation (Myerson 1999): “When elected leaders use political power for their own profit, we call it corruption or abuse of power, or in its most extreme form, tyranny. One of the basic motivations of democracy is the hope that electoral competition should reduce such political abuse of power, below what would occur under an authoritarian system, just as market competition reduces oligopolistic profits below monopoly levels” • What we want is: • An explicit model of electoral agency: a) based on parsimonious motivational assumptions, b) allowing for moral hazard on behalf of elected representatives, and c) allowing voters to select representatives through elections (Austen-Smith & Banks 1989, Banks & Sundaram 1993, Besley 2006) • Data on how real voters behave in situations resembling such a model.

  3. Model (1) • Two stages t=(1,2) with an election in between. • Incumbents are of two possible types i {g,b}. • Let {s,1} signify a productivity parameter with 0<s<d<1, where d is a discount factor. • At the beginning of t=1 random draws determine the type of the first stage incumbent and the nature of the productivity shock for both stages, with commonly known probabilities Pr(i=g)=p and Pr(=s)=q. • Type and productivity is private information to the incumbent. • Let q > ½ by assumption. • The t=1 incumbent selects public production for t=1, and production is publicly announced. • There is an election at the end of t=1. • If the challenger wins, challenger type is randomly determined at the beginning of t=2, with commonly known probability Pr(i=g)=p. • If the challenger looses, the t=1 incumbent continues as incumbent in t=2. • The t=2 incumbent selects public production for t=2. Production is publicly announced, payoffs are distributed and the game ends.

  4. Model (2) • Let payoff to an incumbent of type b be Vb=r1+r2, where rt is rents (diversion of public funds for private ends) in stage t • Let the type g incumbent set rt=0 for t=(1,2) • Let voter payoff be Ut=(1- )y+xt, where  is the tax rate, y is income before tax, xt is public production in stage t, and >1 • Let the budget restriction of the incumbent be (y-rt)=xt. • Finally, let maximal rents equal rt= y. • It follows readily that a b-type incumbent always extracts maximal rents in t=2. • Note also that r1= y dominates r1=0 for a b-type incumbent

  5. Model (3) • It may still be in the interest of a b-type incumbent to mimic a g-type incumbent (by setting 0<r1<ty) in order to be reelected (and take r2=ty) • The central question becomes: what is the rationally updated voter belief after observing production x1=sty? • Let 0<<1 be the probability that a b-type incumbent facing =1 mimics a g-type incumbent facing =s • Bayes rule now provides an answer: Now, assuming voters use pure cutoff strategies; in which they reelect only if P>p, we appreciate that as long as q > ½ all incumbents that produces either x1=sty or x1=ty will be reelected unanimously while no incumbent that produces x1=0 will get any votes. As long as d>s mimicking is profitable for a b-type incumbent.

  6. Design (1) • q=.55 or q=.85, =.20 • =.23 (Marginal update) or =.59 (Substantial update) • Endowment per stage 100; =1.1; =0.5, s=0.5 • Does update have an effect on behavior? • Does group learning have an effect on behavior? • Do subjects learn over time? • How?

  7. Design (2) To root out social distributive preferences and intentions • Electorates matched in absolute stranger protocol • Politician programmed as an automaton

  8. Non-parametric tests (1) Games 1-7 (2 tailed MW-tests) Update effect (at P=25)Decisive voters0.17 (p=0.09)Voters in electorates 0.14 (p=0.24 )Group effect(at P=25)Marginal update0.12 (p=0.26)Substantial update0.15 (p=0.17)

  9. Non parametric tests (2) Games 1-5 & 16-20 (2 tailed MW tests) Update effect5 first games0.24 (p=0.06)5 last games0.26 (p=0.01) Learning effectMarginal update0.08 (p=0.46 )Substantial update0.14 (p=0.23)

  10. Non-parametric tests (3) Average mistakes (decisions): Absolute deviations of registered beliefs from equilibrium beliefs

  11. Non-rational learning rules • We look at two variants; fictitious play and payoff reinforcement learning • Fictitious play variable: Dummy that takes value 1 if fictitious beliefs favor equilibrium behavior and zero otherwise. • Uses all games; also test games • Payoff reinforcement: Continuous variable between zero and one that captures reinforcement (of previous payoff experiences) towards equilibrium behavior (Roth & Erev 1995). • Estimated from the first two games with earnings • What is reinforced is actions given states • Strength of attractions is set at 55 (the order of maximal payoffs)

  12. Regression results Update has a significantly positive effect on probability of being in equilibrium (at P1=25) with no control for non-rational learningControlling for non-rational learning, this effect is halved; and becomes far from significantReinforcement has a strong, positive and highly significant effectFictitious play does not have significant effects

  13. Simulations (1) Substantial updateA player facing a sequence of 1.000 independent gamesResults are averaged over 10.000 sequencesParameters; initial attractions; and strength of attractions as in experiment

  14. Simulations (2) Marginal updateA player facing a sequence of 1.000 independent gamesResults are averaged over 10.000 sequencesParameters; initial attractions; and strength of attractions as in experiment

  15. Conclusions • "...the typical citizen drops down to a lower level of mental performance as soon as he enters the political field. He argues and analyzes in a way which he would readily recognize as infantile within the sphere of his real interests. He becomes primitive again. His thinking is associative and affective ... [This] may prove fatal to the nation.“ (Schumpeter 1942:262) • Design: Control for “affective thinking” (distributive social preferences and intentions) • Results: Thinking is “associative”, almost Pavlovian • Under favorable conditions, this does not matter for “the fate of the Nation” (payoff reinforcement looks as if players were playing an equilibrium) • Under less favorable conditions, it matters for “the fate of the Nation” (payoff reinforcement does is not conducive to optimal discipline and selection) • Creates a challenge for field data studies that find a pattern consistent with equilibrium: It need not imply that data were generated by a bayesian perfect equilibrium

More Related