1 / 56

CHAPTER 3

CHAPTER 3. Certainty Equivalents from Utility Theory. 3.1. Certainty Equivalents. Suppose you had 2 choices: a 1 . Flip a fair coin Heads: you get $500, Tails: you get nothing a 2 . $200 for certain: price for selling a 1  p(  ) a 1 a 2 Heads 0.5 500 200 Tails 0.5 0 200

Télécharger la présentation

CHAPTER 3

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. CHAPTER 3 Certainty Equivalents from Utility Theory

  2. 3.1. Certainty Equivalents • Suppose you had 2 choices: • a1. Flip a fair coin Heads: you get $500, Tails: you get nothing • a2. $200 for certain: price for selling a1 •  p() a1 a2 Heads0.5 500 200 Tails 0.5 0 200 • Your sale price of a1 is its certainty equivalence

  3. Certainty Equivalents Definition • A certain payoff which has the same value to the decision maker as an uncertain payoff • a1. Uncertain payoff: Heads: +$500, Tails: 0 • a2. Certain payoff: $X • If X = 0, you will prefer a1 • If X = 500, you will prefer a2 • Certainty Equivalent: Value of X (0  X  500) that makes a1 = a2

  4. Determining & Using CE In general, given 2 choices: • a1. $X with probability p, or $Y with prob. (1 – p) • a2. $Z for certain (X  Z  Y) • The value of Z that makes the 2 options equal to decision maker is the: Certainty equivalent of a1 : CE(a1) • Stochastic problems can be transformed to deterministic equivalent • Criterion: select option aj with maximum CE(aj)

  5. Making Decisions based on CE • Given 4 choices depending on flipping a fair coin •  p() a1 a2 a3 a4 Heads0.5 550 700 400 300 Tails 0.5 0 –100 100 150 CE 200 150 230 220 • a1 is chosen under minimax regret • a2 is chosen under max EV (but highest risk) • a3 is chosen under max certainty equivalent (combines expected value with risk) • a4 is chosen under maximin

  6. Certainty Equivalents & Coherence • The concept of CE provides a coherent approach for evaluating (ranking) decisions • A valid criterion must recommend ranking consistent with the CE options • A coherent criterion must provide the same score for an uncertain option and its certainty equivalent

  7. CE & Coherence Counter-Example • Given: • Option aj has CE(aj) = y*, but • Under criterion C, score C(aj)  C(y*) • We can find y’ such that: • C(aj) = C(y’), y’ > y* • Decision maker (DM) will pay to replace y* by y’ • Next, since C(aj) = C(y’), DM will not mind switching from y’ to aj. • Next, since y* = CE(aj), DM will not mind switching from aj to y*

  8. CE & Coherence Counter-Example • Example shows that an incoherent criterion makes DM a perpetual money-making machine • For coherence: y’ = y* • Any evaluation criterion must be subjected to this coherence test • Can we use only CE criterion for all decision problems? No, only for simple 2-outcome problems

  9. CE for complex problems • Given:  p() a1 Excellent0.1 10,000 Good 0.3 5,000 Average 0.3 1,000 Poor 0.2 – 400 Terrible 0.1 – 3,000 • Evaluating CE(a1) is extremely difficult • Utility theory is used for complex problems

  10. 3.2. Utility Functions • Utility: Relative value (worth) of each payoff to the decision maker • Utility Theory: Transform payoffs into utility scale (0  1) • Utility & Coherence: Expected utility criterion EU(aj) ranking of options is consistent with DM certainty equivalents EU(aj)

  11. Evaluating utility functions • Given:  p() a1 a2 Good 0.3 $1000 $800 Average 0.4 $500 $600 Poor 0.3 $300 $400 • Min payoff = $300, Max payoff = $1000 • Range of payoffs (300  1000) U(300) = 0 U(1000) = 1

  12. Evaluating utility functions • What is CE for: (p = 0.5 of $300, and p = 0.5 of $1000)? • Assume CE = $500 U(500) = 0.5*U(300) + 0.5*U(1000) = 0.5 • For (p = 0.5 of $300, and p = 0.5 of $500) Assume CE = $375 U(375) = 0.5*U(300) + 0.5*U(500) = 0.25 • If equal prob of 500 & 1000 has CE = 700, we get: U(700) = 0.75

  13. Evaluating utility functions • y 300 375 500 700 1000 • U(y) 0 0.25 0.5 0.75 1.0 1 300 375 500 700 1000 y

  14. Converting payoffs to utilities • Utility matrix, using interpolation:  p() a1 a2 Good 0.3 1 0.85 Average 0.4 0.5 0.65 Poor 0.3 0 0.33 EU 0.5 0.61 • Since U(375) = 0.25 & U(500) = 0.5 U(400) = 0.25 + [(400-375)/(500-375)]*(0.5-0.25) = 0.3 • Based on EU, choose a2

  15. Steps in using utility functions • Derive the utility function using simple CE questions • Transform payoffs into utilities • Choose decision with max expected utility

  16. Utility Ex 1: Oil exploration • Decisions: Alternative investment strategies in oil exploration • To evaluate utility, 2 options: a1. Invest $X to explore for oil prob p: you get $Y, prob (1 – p): you get 0 a2. Do not invest • What probability p would make you indifferent?

  17. Utility Ex 2: Education planning • Decisions: Alternative reading improvement programs • Payoff: Average reading performance • Utility function changes slope around national average (50%) Risk = doing worse than national average Shape of utility function indicates risk attitude

  18. 3.3. Risk Attitudes • Given 2 choices: •  p() a1 a2 Heads0.5 500 200 Tails 0.5 0 200 • If 2 options are equivalent to you, i.e., CE(a1) = 200, then CE(a1) = 200 < EV(a1) = 250 • You considered are risk averse (avoider)

  19. Risk Premium • Risk Premium Money DM is willing to pay to avoid uncertainty (risk) RP(y) = EV(y) – CE(y) = 250 – 200 = 50 • 3 risk attitudes: • Risk-Averse: RP(y) > 0 • Risk-Neutral: RP(y) = 0 • Risk-Seeking: RP(y) < 0

  20. Risk-Neutral Utility Function Straight line: EV(y) = CE(y) RP(y) = constant U’(y) = 1, U’’(y) = 0 U(y) 1 0 y ymin ymax

  21. Risk-Averse Utility Function Concave line: EV(y) > CE(y) RP(y) > 0 U’(y) > 0, U’’(y)  0 U(y) 1 y ymin ymax

  22. Risk-Seeking Utility Function Convex line: EV(y) < CE(y) RP(y) < 0 U’(y) > 0, U’’(y)  0 U(y) 1 y ymin ymax

  23. Risk Attitude Example • Given 2 options: • a1. Uncertain payoff: Heads: +$500, Tails: 0 • a2. Certain payoff: $X What value of X would make 2 options equivalent? • Risk averse: X = 200 RP = 50 • Risk neutral: X = 250 RP = 0 • Risk seeking: X = 300 RP = – 50

  24. Applications of Risk Attitude • Risk Aversion Most common approach in significant decisions • Risk neutrality Corresponds to expected value criterion. Should be used in routine, non-significant decisions • Risk attitude may: - change over time - increase with increasing capital

  25. Risk Attitude vs. payoff range y • A payoff consists of both: • Certain amount y • Uncertain amount   << y, mean = 0, variance = 2, • RP( + y) = EV( + y) – CE( + y) = y – CE( + y) • Risk attitude is: • Decreasing if RP(+y) decreases as y increases • constant if RP(+y) is constant as y increases • Increasing if RP(+y) increases as y increases

  26. Risk Attitude vs. payoff range y • Constant risk attitude (premium) Constantly risk-averse U(y) = a – be– ry, r > 0, a & b constants Constantly risk-neutral U(y) = a + by, a & b constants Constantly risk-averse U(y) = a + be– ry, r < 0, a & b constants

  27. Risk Attitude vs. payoff range y • Decreasing risk attitude Risk aversion (premium) decreases with increasing capital U(y) = – e– ay – be– cy, a > 0, bc > 0 • Decreasing risk attitude Risk aversion (premium) proportional to y RP( + y) = a + by

  28. Risk Aversion Function • r(y) = – U’’(y)/U’(y) • RP( + y)  0.5 2 r(y) • Example Given: U(y) = a + by – cy2, b, c > 0, 0 < y < b/2c U’(y) = b – 2cy U’’(y) = – 2c r(y) = 2c/(b – 2cy) RP( + y) = c2/(b – 2cy) > 0 (increasing risk attitude)

  29. 3.4. Theoretical Assumptions of Utility • Preceding sections: • How utility works • This section: • Why utility works • Theoretical basis • Basic assumptions

  30. Notation • Prospect Aj n payoffs, Yi, each with probability pji, i = 1…n payoff Y1 Y2 … Yn probability pj1 pj2 … pjn Aj = (pj1, Y1; pj2, Y2; … ; pjn, Yn)

  31. Notation • Compound Prospect Ck m prospects, Aj, each with probability qkj, j = 1…m prospect A1 A2 … Am probability qk1 qk2 … qkm Ck = (qk1, A1; qk2, A2; … ; qkm, Am)

  32. Notation example • A1: fair coin Heads (p11 = 0.5)  Y1 = 20 Tails: (p12 = 0.5)  Y2 = – 10 • A2: bent coin Heads (p21 = 0.3)  Y1 = 20 Tails: (p22 = 0.7)  Y2 = – 10 • C1: fair die even: 2, 4, 6 (q11 = 0.5)  A1 Odd: 1, 3, 5 (q12 = 0.5)  A2

  33. Assumption 1 (Structure) • It is sufficient to describe the choices open to the decision maker in terms of payoff values and their associated probabilities • Reducing the problem to prospects and compound prospects captures all that is essential to the decision maker • Temporal resolution of uncertainty: The decision maker may choose between 2 alternatives with exactly the same payoffs and probabilities based on different payoff times

  34. Assumption 2 (Ordering) • The decision maker may express preference or indifference between any pair of payoffs • Notation Y1> Y2 Y1 is preferred to Y2 Y1 Y2 Y1 is preferred to or same as Y2 Y2 is not preferred to Y1 Y* = best payoff, Y* = worst payoff • Transitivity: If A1 A2 and A2 A3 then A1 A3

  35. Assumption 3 (Reduction of Compound Prospects) • Any compound prospect should be indifferent to its equivalent simple prospect Ck (qk1, A1; qk2, A2; … ; qkm, Am)  [qk1(p11, Y1; p12, Y2; … ; p1n, Yn); qk2(p21, Y1; p22, Y2; … ; p2n, Yn); . . . qkm(pm1, Y1; pm2, Y2; … ; pmn, Yn)]  (p'k1, Y1; p'k2, Y2; … ; p'km, Ym) Where p'kj = qk1p1j + qk2p2j + . . . + qkmpmj

  36. Assumption 3 example • C1: fair die q1j Aj p1j Y1 p2j Y2 q11 = 0.5  A1: fair coin0.5 20 0.5 –10 q12 = 0.5  A2: bent coin0.3 20 0.7 –10 • C1  (0.5, A1; 0.5, A2)  [0.5(0.5, 20; 0.5, –10); 0.5(0.3, 20; 0.7, –10)]  [(0.25 + 0.15), 20; (0.25 + 0.35), –10]  [0.4, 20; 0.6, –10]

  37. Assumption 3 & Coherence • Assumption 3 indicates ideal level of coherence • No preference for single or multiple steps • Assumption 3 does not apply if • Preference for multiple steps, game atmosphere • Special type of risk in a particular business

  38. Assumption 4 (Continuity) • Every payoff Yi can be considered a certainty equivalent for a prospect: [ui, Y*; (1 – ui), Y*], 0  ui 1 Y* = best payoff, Y* = worst payoff • Since each uncertain prospect has an equivalent certain payoff (CE), • then each certain payoff has an equivalent uncertain prospect

  39. Assumption 4 (Continuity) • Since Yi = CE of: Ai [ui, Y*; (1 – ui), Y*], 0  ui 1 Y* = best payoff, Y* = worst payoff • ui(Yi) = probability of Y* that makes Ai Yi • ui(Y*) = 1 for max payoff • ui(Y*) = 0 for min payoff • ui(Yi) = utility of payoffYi

  40. Assumption 5 (Substitutability) • In any prospect, Yi can be substituted by its a uncertain equivalent: [ui, Y*; (1 – ui), Y*] • Yi and [ui, Y*; (1 – ui), Y*] are indifferent, not only when considered alone, but also when considered part of a more complicated prospect • Similar to coherence related to minimax regret: ranking of alternatives should not change if other alternatives are added

  41. Assumption 6 (Transitivity of Prospects) • The decision maker can express preference or indifference between all pairs of prospects. • Extension of Assumption 2 (payoff preference) • Any prospect can be expressed in terms of Y* & Y* A1 (p11, Y1; p12, Y2; … ; p1n, Yn)  (p11, [u1, Y*; (1 – u1), Y*]; . . . )  (p1, Y*; p2, Y*) Where p1 = p11u1 + p12u2 + . . . + p1nun

  42. Assumption 7 ( Monotonicity) • A prospect Ar [pr, Y*; (1 – pr), Y*] is preferred or indifferent to (  ) prospect As [ps, Y*; (1 – ps), Y*] iff: pr ps • Given 2 options with the same 2 alternative payoffs, we prefer the option with higher probability of the better payoff • For options with several payoffs: Ar Asiff: pr1 u1 + pr2 u2 + . . . + pr1 un ps1 u1 + ps2 u2 + . . . + ps1 un EU(Ar)  EU(As)

  43. 3.5. Some Caveats in Interpreting Utility • Utility theory is normative: • It suggests what people should do to be coherent • Does not describe what they actually do • In practice, people violate expected utility criterion depending on circumstances

  44. Utilities do not add up • Expected utility of a sum of payoff is not equal to sum of expected utilities U(A + B)  U(A) + U(B) • Unless the decision maker is risk-neutral

  45. Utility differences do not express strength of preferences • Given: Y1 > Y2 > Y3 > Y4 , and U(Y1 – Y2 ) > U(Y3 – Y4) This does not imply moving from Y2 to Y1 is preferable to moving from Y4 to Y3. • Utility provides an “ordinal” scale, not an “interval” scale • Ordinal: teacher evaluation, (7 – 6)  (9 – 8) • Interval: weight in kilograms, (60 – 50) = (80 – 70)

  46. Utilities are not comparable from person to person • If 2 people assign the same utility to a prospect, we cannot say it has the same worth to each • Utility values are completely subjective • Utilities of different people cannot be added to determine group preferences

  47. 3.6. Issues in the assessment of risk • Utility assessment is not a natural activity for DM • Unnatural setup may results in wrong utility values, and wrong decisions • Method of assessment must be as close as possible to real problem

  48. Basic utility assessment process • Given 2 options: • X  certain payoff • Y  probability p of payoff G (gain) probability (1 – p) of payoff L (loss) • Four variables • X, Y, G, L • Fix any 3 variables, ask DM to supply the 4th

  49. 4 Response modes • Certainty equivalence: DM gives X • Probability equivalence: DM gives p • Gain equivalence: DM gives G • Loss equivalence: DM gives L • First 2 methods most common

  50. Level of probabilty • 4 variables: X, p, G, L • Except in probability equivalence methods, p is given • Small probabilities get distorted • p = 1 – p = 0.5 seems to be least biased

More Related