1 / 26

Review

Review We can use truth tables to evaluate the validity of arguments. Example: P1: B(C v A) P2: B v C C: A B(C v A) / B v C // A Like This B(C v A) / B v C / A T T T T T T T T T T T T T F T T T F T T F T T T T F T T F F F F T T F F F T T T T F T T T

jana
Télécharger la présentation

Review

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Review We can use truth tables to evaluate the validity of arguments. Example: P1: B(C v A) P2: B v C C: A B(C v A) / B v C // A

  2. Like This B(C v A) / B v C / A T T T T T T T T T T T T T F T T T F T T F T T T T F T T F F F F T T F F F T T T T F T T T F T T T F F T T F F T F T T F F F T F T F F F F F F F Row 2 proves that the argument is invalid (so does row 6)

  3. Indirect Truth Tables Consider an argument symbolized thusly: P1. (B * D)~C P2. D v B C1. ~CB If we were to use a full truth table to evaluate its validity, we would need 8 rows

  4. Shorter Method • There is a shorter way to test validity: Start by assuming the argument is invalid Represent this by putting T’s under the main logical operator of the premises and an F under the main logical operator of the conclusion

  5. Like This (B * D)~C / D v B // ~CB T T F Next, determine the truth values of the other statements, given the truth values of the premises and conclusion: (B * D)~C / D v B // ~CB F F T TT F T T F TF F F

  6. Notice • We have a consistent assignment of truth values that makes the premises true and the conclusion false • Therefore, the argument is invalid, as assumed

  7. Another Example Consider this argument: P1: C(BD) P2: ~(BD) C1: ~C C(BD) / ~(BD) // ~C T T F

  8. A Contradiction! C(BD) / ~(BD) // ~C T T TF F T T F F FT Notice that we cannot give a consistent assignment of truth values. The first premise, if we assume it to be true, is false. Because we get a contradiction, the argument is valid.

  9. A Complication • Sometimes there is more than one way for the premises to be true and the conclusion false Example: A v B / BA / ~A v ~B // ~B * A There are three ways the conclusion can be false!

  10. See? A v B / BA / ~A v ~B // ~B * A T T T TF F F T T T FT F T T T T FT F F To test the validity of the argument, we need to see if we can find a consistent set of truth value assignments on at least one of the three rows

  11. Start with the First Row A v B / BA / ~A v ~B // ~B * A F T F TF F F FT F T FT F F Notice that we have a contradiction in the first premise: we assumed it is true, but that assumption is inconsistent with the truth values of A and B on that row

  12. Can we Stop? • No! That there is a contradiction on the first row does not prove the argument is valid, for there may be a consistent assignment of truth values on the other two rows. Remember, we are looking for at least one consistent assignment of truth values to prove the argument invalid

  13. Go To Second Row A v B / BA / ~A v ~B // ~B * A F T F TF F F FT T FT FT F T FT F F We have a contradiction in the third premise on the second row. So me must look at the third row

  14. Go to Third Row A v B / BA / ~A v ~B // ~B * A F T F TF F F FT T FT FT F T T T F FT F F We have a contradiction in the second premise. Because there is a contradiction on every row, we know the argument is valid (there are no rows with a consistent assignment of truth values that makes the premises true and the conclusion false)

  15. A Good Procedure to Follow • Determine the number of ways the conclusion can be false and represent them with a truth table under the conclusion • Start with the first row and check if a contradiction is produced. If so, go to the second row. If not, stop; the argument is invalid • Repeat the second step until there are no more rows. If a contradiction is produced on every row, the argument is valid.

  16. Testing Consistency with Indirect Truth Tables • We can determine whether a set of statements is consistent by first assuming that all the statements are true Example: ~AB/ B(~CA)/ B~C/ ~A T T T T Next, compute the truth values of the other statements, based on this assumption

  17. Like This ~AB/ B(~CA)/ B~C/ ~A TF TT T T TFF F T T TF TF Notice that there is a contradiction in the second statement. Also notice that we need only one row, because there is only one way for the last statement to be true (and thus the assumption that all of them are true). Because we derived a contradiction, the statements cannot all be true—thus, the statements are inconsistent.

  18. A Complication • Sometimes there is more than one way for a set of statements to come out true Example: ~A v (B * C)/ ~C v ~A/ ~BA T T T In this case, there are three ways each of the statements can be true (to see this, recall the truth tables for disjunction and conditional)

  19. What to do? Select one of the statements and represent the three ways it can be true. Let’s select the last statement ~A v (B * C)/ ~C v ~A/ ~BA T T FT T F FT T T TF T T

  20. Look at the First Row ~A v (B * C)/ ~C v ~A/ ~BA TF T T T TF FT T F FT T T TF T T Notice that we do not have to assign a truth value to C in the first row, because the first two statements will come out true regardless. Since there is a consistent assignment of truth values on at least one row, the statements are consistent.

  21. The Procedure for Testing Consistency • Look at the statements and pick the one that has the fewest number of ways it can come out true. • Represent those ways with a truth table under the statement • Start with the first row and determine the truth values of the other statements. • If no contradiction is produced, stop. The statements are consistent. If not, go to the second row and repeat the previous step • If a contradiction is produced on every row, the statements are inconsistent.

  22. Common Valid and Invalid Argument Forms • An argument form is valid just in case every substitution instance of that form is such that it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false • In the language of truth tables, there are no rows where the premises are true and the conclusion false

  23. Continued • How shall we define an invalid argument form? • Should we say that an argument form is invalid just in case every substitution instance of that form is invalid (e.g. there is at least one row on the truth table where the premises are true and the conclusion false?)

  24. No • Here’s why: consider this argument form pq q p It is in an invalid form, but there are substitution instances of the form that are valid!

  25. Huh? • See? Consider this substitution instance (A v ~A)B B (A v ~A) It is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false, because the conclusion is a tautology (it is true on every row of the truth table)

  26. So… • Let’s define an invalid argument form this way: An argument form is invalid just in case there is at least one substitution instance of that form that is invalid. In the language of truth tables, there is at least one substitution instance where at least one row has true premises and a false conclusion

More Related