1 / 27

Bjørn Jespersen TU Ostrava Dept. Computer Science bjornjespersen@gmail.com

D oubleplusungood double privation and multiply modified artefact properties Tutorial in two parts Deparment of Computer Science Technical University of Ostrava 26 February & 1 March 2013. Bjørn Jespersen TU Ostrava Dept. Computer Science bjornjespersen@gmail.com. relevant TIL literature.

sahara
Télécharger la présentation

Bjørn Jespersen TU Ostrava Dept. Computer Science bjornjespersen@gmail.com

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Doubleplusungooddouble privation and multiply modified artefact propertiesTutorial in two partsDeparment of Computer ScienceTechnical University of Ostrava26 February & 1 March 2013 Bjørn Jespersen TU Ostrava Dept. Computer Science bjornjespersen@gmail.com

  2. relevant TIL literature • A new logic of technical malfunction (with M. Carrara), StudiaLogica, DOI 10.1007/s11225-012-9397-8, forthcoming • Alleged(ly) in: The Logica Yearbook 2012, V. Punčochář, P. Švarný (eds.), College Publications, London, forthcoming • Alleged assassins: realist and constructivist semantics for modal modifiers(with G. Primiero), LNCS 7758 (2013), 94-114 • Two kinds of procedural semantics for privative modification (with G. Primiero), LNAI 6284 (2010), 252-71 • Double privation and multiply modified properties (with M. Carrara), in submission • Left subsectivity, in submission

  3. the problem If a property F has been multiplymodified in this or that manner, is an individual a that has the so modified property an F?  0M’ 0M 0F , ‘a happy bald child’ F/() (); M, M’/(() ()) () 0M* 0M 0F, ‘a very happy child’ M* /((() ()) /(() ())) (() ())

  4. subsective, privative, modal 0Ms 0Fwt0a 0Mp 0Fwt0a   0Fwt0a0 0Fwt0a A modal modifier, preliminarily speaking, is one that oscillates between being subsective and being privative. Subsectionsays what something is; privation, what something isnot; and modal modification, what something may be.

  5. two main findings + main hypothesis + open question • Problem: the received rule for single privative modification is too strong when extended to multiple privation. • Solution: replace propositional (Boolean) negation by property negation in order to operate on the contraries of properties. Intuitive, since something that operates on properties (a modifier) is replaced by something else that also operates on properties (property negation). • Result: a pair of privative modifiers is equivalent to one modal modifier. • Hypothesis: the logic of multiple privation is a logic of contraries. • Open question: where does logic end and semantics begin?

  6. double privation, 1st and 2ndorder (TIL: degree): examples • 0Almost* 0Finished0Meal • 0Almost* 0Half0Pound • 0Former0Apparent 0Heir • 0Former* 0Apparent0Heir

  7. modifiers of propositions, of properties, of other modifiers DEFINITION 1 (first- and second-order modifier). Apropositional modifier is of type (), forming a proposition from a proposition. A property modifieris of type (), forming a property from a property, and is thus a first-order (in TIL: first-degree) modifier. A modifier of property modifiersis of type (() ()), i.e. a second-order (in TIL: second-degree) modifier. 

  8. subsective modifier DEFINITION 2 (subsective property modifier). Let M/(); let gsrange over (()); let x range over ; let F/; let /((() (()))): it is true or else false that a particular modifier Mis an element of a particular set of modifiers. Then: M is subsective w.r.t. F iff Mg [0Req0F [gs0F]]. 

  9. double privation as double Boolean negation [[0Mp [0Mp0F]]wt0a]  [[0[00F]]wt0a]  [0 [0[0Fwt 0a]]]  [0Fwt0a] [[[0Mp* 0Mp] 0F]wt0a]  [[[00] 0F]wt0a]  [0[0[0Fwt0a]]]  [0Fwt0a]

  10. what just went wrong? • 0Fake0Fake 0Fwt0a, [[[0Fake* 0Fake] 0F]wt0a] ought obviously not to translate into 0 00Fwt0a there’s negation, and there’s negation: • a is a non-F :property negation • Not (a is an F) :Boolean/propositional/truth-value negation

  11. property negation (informally) • The sentences “It is a not-white log” and “It is not a white log” do not imply one another’s truth. For if “It is a not-white log” is true, it must be a log: but that which is not a white log need not be a log at all.(Prior Analytics I, 46, 1) • From the fact that John is not dishonest we cannot conclude that John is honest, but only that he is possibly so. (La Palma Reyes et al. 1999, p. 255.)

  12. non-Boolean negation [[0Mp’ [0Mp0F]]wt0a]  [[0non [0Mp0F]]wt0a]  [[0non [0non 0F]]wt0a]  ?

  13. privative modifier DEFINITION 3 (privative property modifier). Let M/(); let gprange over (()); let x range over ; let F/; let /((() (()))). Then: M is privative w.r.t. F iff Mgp[0Req [0non 0F] [gp0F]]. From Def. 3 we obtain the following elimination rule for privative modifiers Mp: 0Mpfwtx  0nonfwt x

  14. modal modifier DEFINITION 4 (modal property modifier). Let M/(); let gmrange over (()); let x range over ; let F/; let /((() (()))); let /(()) and /(()). Then: M is modal w.r.t. F iff M  gm0Reqwtx0w´0t´0Mm 0Fwt x 0Fw’t’ x0w´´0t´´0Mm 0Fwt x0non 0Fw´´t´´ xgm 0F.  From Def. 4 we obtain the following conditional elimination rule for Mm: 0Mmfwt0a  w’ 0t’ 0Mmfwt0afw’t’0a 0w’’ 0t’’ 0Mmfwt0a0nonfw’’t’’0a Gloss: “From a being an 0Mmf at w, t, infer that there is a w´, t´ such that if a is an 0Mmf at w, t then a is an f at w´, t´ and that there is an alternative w´´, t´´ such that if a is an 0Mmf at w, t then a is a 0nonfat w´´, t´´.”

  15. rule 1 [[0Ms0F]wt0a]  [0Fwt0a]

  16. rule 2 [[0Mp0F]wt0a]  [[0non0F]wt0a]

  17. rule 3 [[0Ms’ [0Ms0F]]wt0a]  [[0Ms0F]wt0a] (1) [0Fwt0a]

  18. rule 4 [[0Ms’ [0Mp0F]]wt0a]  [[0Mp0F]wt0a] (2) 0non 0Fwt0a

  19. rule 5 [[0Mp[0Ms0F]]wt0a]  [[0non [0Ms0F]]wt0a]

  20. rule 6 [[0Mp’ [0Mp0F]]wt0a]  [[0non [0Mp0F]]wt0a]/[[0Mp’ [0non 0F]]wt0a]  [[0non’ [0non 0F]]wt0a]

  21. rule 7 [[[0Ms* 0Ms] 0F]wt0a]  [[0Ms0F]wt0a] (1) [0Fwt0a]

  22. rule 8 [[[0Mp* 0Mp] 0F]wt0a]  [[[0non* 0Mp] 0F]wt0a]/ [[[0Mp* 0non] 0F]wt0a]  [[[0non* 0non] 0F]wt0a]

  23. rule 9 [[[0Ms* 0Mp] 0F]wt0a]  [[0Mp0F]wt0a] (2) [[0non0F]wt0a]

  24. rule 10 [[[0Mp* 0Ms] 0F]wt0a]  [[[0non* 0Ms] 0F]wt0a]

  25. the logic of non (intuitive sketch) Formally, non takes a (modified or basic) property to one of its contraries, leaving it open which particular contrary. Imagine a residing in the capital of some country. When a leaves the capital, a moves to a town in the province. When a leaves that town, a has the choice between returning to the capital or going to some other town in the province. From the point of view of the first town a goes to, its complement includes both the capital and all the other towns in the province. So each new privation introduces a shift in perspectiveas to what the complement is. It is crucial not to confuse non, which operates on properties, with the complement function \, which operates on sets. The complement of a complement is the original set, thereby reinstalling the problem with Boolean negation.

  26. conclusions • The general rule of privation replaces the property constructed by 0Mp0F by the property constructed by 0non0F • A pair of privative modifiers is equivalent to one modal modifier • The present framework serves an extensional, set-theoretic purpose: is a in or out? • Further research will be hyperintensional, semantic: ‘is an almost finished meal’versus ‘is almost half a pound’

  27. exercise (1) What are the various ways of carving up the scopes of the adjective ‘doubleplusungood’? (Orwell, 1984, 1949) (2) Is any one analysis superior? doubleplusungood

More Related