1 / 31

A propositional world

A propositional world. Ofer Strichman Joint work with Randal Bryant and Sanjit Seshia School of Computer Science, Carnegie Mellon University. Integrated decision procedures in Theorem-Provers. Deciding a combination of theories is the key for automation in Theorem Provers:

Télécharger la présentation

A propositional world

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. A propositional world Ofer Strichman Joint work with Randal Bryant and Sanjit Seshia School of Computer Science, Carnegie Mellon University

  2. Integrated decision procedures in Theorem-Provers Deciding a combination of theories is the key for automation in Theorem Provers: Boolean operators, Bit-vector, Sets, Linear-Arithmetic, Uninterpreted functions, More … Bit-Vector operators Linear Arithmetic Uninterpreted functions f(f(x)-f(y)) != f(z) & y <=x + 2 | b & 3 > 10 Normally, each theory is solved with its own decision procedure and the results are combined (Shostak, Nelson..).

  3. Integrated decision procedures in Theorem-Provers All of these theories, except linear arithmetic, have known efficient direct reductions to propositional logic. Thus, reducing linear arithmetic to propositional logic will: 1. Enable integration of theories in the propositional logic level. 2. Potentially be faster than known techniques.

  4. Linear Arithmetic and its sub-theories 2x –3y +5z < 0 5x + 2w 2 • Some useful methods for solving a conjunction of linear • arithmetic expressions: • Simplex, Elliptic curve • Variable Elimination Methods (Hodes, Fourier-Motzkin,..) • Shostak’sloop residues • Separation theory: Bellman / Pratt ... • ...

  5. x 3 1 z y -1 A decision procedure for separation theory Separation predicates have the form x > y + c where x,y are real variables, and c is a constant Pratt [73] (/Bellman[57]): Given a set of conjuncted separation predicates  1. Construct the `inequality graph’ 2.  is satisfiable iff there is no cycle with non-negative accumulated weight : (x > z +3 z>y –1 y > x+1)

  6. Handling disjunctions through case splitting • All previously mentioned algorithms handle disjunctions • by splitting the formula. • This can be thought of as a two stage process: • Convert formula to Disjunctive Normal Form (DNF) • Solve each clause separately, until satisfying one of them. (A common improvement: split ‘when needed’) Case splitting is frequently the bottleneck of the procedure

  7. So what can be done against case-splitting ? Answer: Split the domain, not the formula. Given a formula , this transformation can be done if ’ s.t. |= |=’, and ’ is decidable under a finite domain. • When is this possible? •  enjoys the ‘Small model property’, or • Tailor-made reduction

  8. SAT vs. infinite-state decision procedures With finite instantiation (e.g. SAT), we split the domain. Infinite state decision procedures split the formula. So what’s the big difference ?

  9. 1. Pruning. 2. Learning. 3. Guidance (prioritizing internal steps) SAT vs. infinite-state decision procedures Three mechanisms, crucial for efficient decision making: SAT has a significant advantage in all three.

  10. x 0 1 . (x  y) . . Backtrack y 1 0 Pruned! SAT vs. infinite-state decision procedures (1/4) 1. Pruning SAT: each clause c prunes up to 2|v|-|c| states. |v|=1000, |c| =2 Pruning 2998states Others: ? (stops when finds a satisfiable clause)

  11. SAT vs. infinite-state decision procedures (2/4) 2. Learning SAT: Partial assignments that lead to a conflict are recorded and hence not repeated. Others: (depends on decision procedure) - Adding proved sub-goals as antecedents to new sub-goals - …

  12. SAT vs. infinite-state decision procedures (3/4) 3. Guidance (prioritizing internal steps) Consider 1 2, where 1is unsat and hard, and 2is sat and easy. With proper guidance, a theorem prover should start from 2. Guidance requires efficient estimation: - How hard it is to solve each sub-formula? - To what extent will it simplify the rest of the proof?

  13. SAT vs. infinite-state decision procedures (4/4) 3. Guidance (cont’d) “..To what extent will it simplify the rest of the proof?” SAT: Guidance through decision heuristics (e.g. DLIS). (x  y  z) (x  v) (~x  ~z) Estimating simplification by counting literals in each phase Others: Expression ordering, ...

  14. Example: Equality Logic with Uninterpreted Functions (1/3) Equality Logic with Uninterpreted Functions: (Uninterpreted functions are reducible to equality logic. Thus, we can concentrate on equality logic) Traditional infinite-state decision procedure: Congruence Closurewith case splitting.

  15. Example: Equality Logic (2/3) • Since 1998, several groups devised finite-state decision procedures • for this theory: • Goel et. al. (CAV’98) – Boolean encoding and BDDs • Bryant et. al.(CAV’99) – Positive-equality + finite instantiation • Pnueli et. al. (CAV’99) – Small domains instantiation • Bryant et. al.(CAV’00) – Boolean encoding with explicit constraints

  16. x exz exy z y eyz Example: Equality Logic (3/3) Bryant et. al. (CAV’00): Add transitivity constraints to the formula. Let (x=y, y=z, x=z) be the equality predicates in . 1. Construct the equality graph. 2. Impose transitivity on cycles: exy + eyz +exz  2 The resulting formula is propositional BDDs , SAT, etc.

  17. This work Extends the results of Bryant et.al. to a Boolean combination of: • Separation predicates: • Separation predicates for integers: • Linear arithmetic: • Integer linear arithmetic: Done

  18. Usability Separation predicates: “Most verification conditions involving inequalities are separation predicates” [Pratt, 1973]: Array bounds checks, tests on index variables, timing constraints, worst execution time analysis, etc. Linear arithmetic: All of the above + … + Linear programming, + Integer Linear programming.

  19. Reducing separation predicates to propositional logic (1/6) A. Normalize (example): : f(x) > f(y+1) 1. Uninterpreted functions  equality logic : (x=y+1f1=f2)(f1>f2) 2. Normal form xy+1 f1=f2 : (x>y+1 y>x-1(f1 f2 f2 f1)) (f1>f2) Now  has no negations and only the ‘>’ and ‘’ predicate symbols.

  20. x 3 1 z y -1 x -3 -1 z y 1 Reducing separation predicates to propositional logic (3/6) B. Encode + construct graph (example): : (x > z +3  (z>y –1 yx+1)) Transitivity constraints  )) ( ’:   ( and its dual: Separation graph:

  21. x 3 1 z y -1 x -3 -1 z y 1 Reducing separation predicates to propositional logic (5/6) C. Add transitivity constraints for each simple cycle (example): Transitivity constraints )) (   (  ’: (( )) )) (   (  ’:  

  22. ..... ..... Compact representation of constraints (1/4) n diamonds  2nsimple cycles. Can we do better than that ? In most cases - yes. e.g. If the diamonds are ‘balanced’ (c1 +c2 =c3 +c4)  O(n) constraints c2 c1 c1+ c2 c4 c3

  23. Compact representation of constraints (2/4) Chordal graphs: each cycle of size greater than 3, has a ‘chord’. G: In the equality predicates case: Let C be a cycle in G Let  be an assignment that violates C’s transitivity ( |C) Theorem: there exists a cycle c of size 3 in G s.t.  | c Conclusion: add transitivity constraints only for triangles. Now only a polynomial no. of constraints is required.

  24. c2 c1 c1+ c2 c3 c4 c5 Compact representation of constraints (3/4) • Our case is more complicated: • G is directed • G is a multi-graph • Edges have weights • There are two types of edges G is chordal iff: Every directed cycle of size greater than 3 has a chord which ‘accumulates’ the weight of the path between its ends.

  25. ..... 2. If there are uniform weights c1 and c2, c1c2 on top and bottom paths  O(n2) constraints c1 c1 c1 c1 c2 c2 c2 c2 Compact representation of constraints (4/4) Complexity of making the graph chordal: 1. If the diamonds are ‘balanced’  O(n) constraints 3. Worst case  O(2n)

  26. Extension to integer variables (1/2) (c is an integer) Given  with integer separation predicates, derive R: • Declare all variables as real. • For each predicate x>y + c, add a constraint • x > y + c  x y + c + 1 Theorem:  is satisfiable iff R is satisfiable

  27. Experimental results (1/3) d=2 ..... n diamonds Each diamond has 2d edges Top and bottom paths in each diamond are disjuncted. There are 2nconjuncted cycles. By adjusting the weights, we ensured that there is a single satisfying assignment.

  28. Experimental results (2/3) To be continued...

  29. Experimental results (3/3) To be continued... The procedure has recently been integrated into SyMP and Euclid. We currently experiment with real software verification problems.

  30. c1 c3 c2 Next: Linear Arithmetic (1/2) Separation predicates: c x > y + c y x Adding constraints according to accumulated cycle weight: The testc1 + c2 + c3 > 0 results in a yes/no answer

  31. x 2z + c 3 y 2 Next: Linear Arithmetic (2/2) Linear Arithmetic: 2z + c x > y + 2z + c y x The test1 + 2 + 3 > 0 results in a new predicate! Shostak[81]: ‘Deciding linear inequalities by computing loop residues’ - Determine a fixed variable order - Represent each predicate by its two ‘highest’ variables This procedure guarantees termination.

More Related