1 / 52

How to get the most out of null results using Bayes

How to get the most out of null results using Bayes. Zoltán Dienes. The problem: Does a non-significant result count as evidence for the null hypothesis or as no evidence either way?. Geoff Cummin: http://www.latrobe.edu.au/psy/esci/index.html. The solutions: Power Interval estimates

bethan
Télécharger la présentation

How to get the most out of null results using Bayes

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. How to get the most out of null results using Bayes Zoltán Dienes

  2. The problem: Does a non-significant result count as evidence for the null hypothesis or as no evidence either way?

  3. Geoff Cummin: http://www.latrobe.edu.au/psy/esci/index.html

  4. The solutions: Power Interval estimates Bayes Factors

  5. Problems with Power Power depends on specifying the minimal effect of interest (which may be poorly specified by the theory) Power cannot make use of your actual data to determine the sensitivity of those data Confidence intervals solve the second problem Bayes Factors can solve both problems By making use of the full range of predictions of the theory, it makes maximal use of the data in assessing the sensitivity of the data in distinguishing your theory from the null A Bayes Factor can show strong evidence for the null hypothesis over your theory, when it is impossible to say anything using power or confidence intervals

  6. The four principles of inference by intervals: Minimal interesting value Null region Difference between means -> 0 If the 95% confidence/ credibility/ likelihood interval is completely contained in this region, conclude there is good evidence that population value lies in null region – accept the null region hypothesis If the interval is completely outside this region, conclude there is good evidence that population value lies outside null region – reject the null region hypothesis If the upper limit of the interval is below the minimal interesting value, conclude there is evidence against a theory postulating a positive difference If the interval includes both null and theoretically interesting values, the data are insensitive

  7. The Bayes Factor

  8. Cat hypothesis Devil hypothesis

  9. If a cat, you lose finger only 1/10 of time If a devil, you will lose finger 9/10 of time

  10. Evidence supports the theory that most strongly predicted it

  11. Evidence supports the theory that most strongly predicted it John puts his hand in the box and loses a finger. Which hypothesis is most strongly supported, the cat hypothesis or the devil hypothesis?

  12. Evidence supports a theory that most strongly predicted it John puts his hand in the box and loses a finger. Which hypothesis is most strongly supported, the cat hypothesis or the devil hypothesis? Cat hypothesis predicts this result with probability = 1/10 Devil hypothesis predicts this result with probability = 9/10

  13. Evidence supports a theory that most strongly predicted it John puts his hand in the box and loses a finger. Which hypothesis is most strongly supported, the cat hypothesis or the devil hypothesis? Cat hypothesis predicts this result with probability = 1/10 Devil hypothesis predicts this result with probability = 9/10 Strength of evidence for devil over cat hypothesis = 9/10 divided by 1/10 = 9

  14. The evidence is nine times as strong for the devil over the cat hypothesis OR Bayes Factor (B) = 9

  15. Consider: John does not lose a finger

  16. Consider: John does not lose a finger Now evidence strongly supports cat over devil hypothesis (BF = 9 for cat over devil hypothesis or 1/9 for devil over cat hypothesis)

  17. Probability of losing finger given cat = 4/10 Probability of losing finger given devil = 6/10 Now if John loses finger strength of evidence for devil over cat = 6/4 = 1.5 Not very strong

  18. We can distinguish: Evidence for cat hypothesis over devil Evidence for devil hypothesis over cat Not much evidence either way.

  19. Bayes factor tells you how strongly the data are predicted by the different theories (e.g. your pet theory versus null hypothesis): B = Probability of your data given your pet theory divided by probability of data given null hypothesis

  20. If B is greater than 1 then the data supported your theory over the null If B is less than 1, then the data supported the null over your theory If B = about 1, experiment was not sensitive. (Automatically get a notion of sensitivity; contrast: just relying on p values in significance testing.) Jeffreys, 1961: Bayes factors more than 3 or less than a 1/3 are substantial

  21. To know which theory data support need to know what the theories predict The null is normally the prediction of e.g. no difference On the null hypothesis only this value is plausible Plausibility 4 -2 0 2 Population difference between conditions

  22. To know which theory data support need to know what the theories predict The null is normally the prediction of e.g. no difference Need to decide what difference or range of differences are consistent with one’s theory Difficult - but forces one to think clearly about one’s theory.

  23. To calculate a Bayes factor must decide what range of differences are predicted by the theory • Uniform distribution • Half normal • Normal

  24. Example: The theory predicts a difference will be in one direction. Subjects give 0-8 ratings in two conditions Plausibility 4 8 -2 0 2 Population difference in means between conditions Maximum difference allowed

  25. Seems more plausible to think the larger effects are less likely than the smaller ones: Plausibility 0 Population difference in means between conditions But how to scale the rate of drop?

  26. Plausibility 0 4 Population difference in means between conditions Implies: Smaller effects more likely than bigger ones; effects bigger than 8 very unlikely

  27. Similar sorts of effects as those predicted in the past have been on the order of a 5% difference between conditions Plausibility 0 5 Population difference in means between conditions Implies: Smaller effects more likely than bigger ones; effects bigger than 10% very unlikely

  28. Plausibility 0 10 5 Difference between conditions

  29. To calculate Bayes factor in a t-test situation Need same information from the data as for a t-test: Mean difference, Mdiff SE of difference, SEdiff

  30. To calculate Bayes factor in a t-test situation Need same information from the data as for a t-test: Mean difference, Mdiff SE of difference, SEdiff Note: t = Mdiff / SEdiff => SEdiff = Mdiff/t

  31. To calculate a Bayes factor: 1) Google “ZoltanDienes” 2) First site to come up is the right one: http://www.lifesci.sussex.ac.uk/home/Zoltan_Dienes/ 3) Click on link to book 4) Click on link to Chapter Four 5) Scroll down and click on “Click here to calculate your Bayes factor!”

  32. http://www.latrobe.edu.au/psy/esci/index.html Bayes p 2.96 .081 4.88 .034 0.52 .74 4.88 .034 2.70 .09 0.46 .817 4.40 .028 1024.6 .001 3.33 .056 4.88 .031 1.73 .279 4.28 .024 2.96 .083 49.86 .002 2.16 .167 2.12 .172 1.01 .387 0.65 .614 0.75 .476 28.00 .006 4.28 .028 49.86 .002 5.60 .024 2.36 .144 1.73 .23 The tai chi of the Bayes factors The dance of the p values

  33. A Bayes Factor requires establishing predicted effect sizes. How? Do digit-colour synesthetes show a Stroop effect on digits? You display: 3 … 4 … 5 … 6 What they see: 3 … 4 … 5 … 6 You get a null effect (incongruent minus congruent RTs) . . . What size effect would be predicted if there were one?

  34. A Bayes Factor requires establishing predicted effect sizes. Do digit-colour synesthetes show a Stroop effect on digits? You display: 3 … 4 … 5 … 6 What they see: 3 … 4 … 5 … 6 You get a null effect (incongruent minus congruent RTs) . . . What size effect would be predicted if there were one? Run normals on a condition in which digits are coloured in the way synesthetes say they are. The Stroop effect is presumably the maximum one could expect synesthetes to show. Use a uniform: Plausibility Effect for normals with real colours 0 Possible population Stroop effects

  35. Another condition in your experiment might help settle expectations: Jiang et al 2012 Obtained significant amount of unconscious knowledge (5%) Conscious knowledge was 6% with a SE of 7%

  36. Another condition in your experiment might help settle expectations: Jiang et al 2012 Obtained significant amount of unconscious knowledge (5%) Conscious knowledge was 6% with a SE of 7% (non-significant) To assess meaning of non-significant result, used a half-normal with SD = 5% BF = 1.25

  37. Another group in your experiment might help settle expectations: Jiang et al 2012 Obtained significant amount of unconscious knowledge (5%) Conscious knowledge was 6% with a SE of 7% Used a half-normal with SD = 5% BF = 1.25 Nothing follows about whether subjects had conscious knowledge or not

  38. If you have a manipulation meant to reduce an effect, effect of manipulation unlikely to be larger than the basic effect e.g. Dienes, Baddeley & Jansari (2012) Predicted sad mood would reduce learning compared to neutral mood So e.g. if on 2-alternative forced choice test, in neutral condition people get 70% correct

  39. If you have a manipulation meant to reduce an effect, effect of manipulation unlikely to be larger than the basic effect e.g. Dienes, Baddeley & Jansari (2012) Predicted sad mood would reduce learning compared to neutral mood So e.g. if on 2-alternative forced choice test, in neutral condition people get 70% correct Sad condition expected to be somewhere between 50 and 70% So effect of mood must be?

  40. My typical practice: • If think of way of determining an approximate expected size of effect • Use half normal with SD = to that typical size • If think of way of determining an approximate upper limit of effect • => Use uniform from 0 to that limit

  41. Moral and inferential paradoxes of orthodoxy: • On the orthodox approach, standardlyyou should plan in advance how many subjects you will run. • If you just miss out on a significant result you are not allowed to just run 10 more subjects and test again. • You are not allowed to run until you get a significant result. • Bayes: It does not matter when you decide to stop running subjects. You can always run more subjects if you think it will help.

  42. Moral paradox: • If p = .07 after running planned number of subjects • If you run more and report significant at 5% you have cheated • If you don’t run more and bin the results you have wasted tax payer’s money and your time, and wasted relevant data • You are morally damned either way • Inferential paradox • Two people with the same data and theories could draw opposite conclusions

  43. Moral and inferential paradoxes of orthodoxy: 2. On the orthodox approach, it matters whether you formulated your hypothesis before or after looking at the data. Post hoc vs planned comparisons Predictions made in advance of rather than before looking at the data are treated differently Bayesian inference: It does not matter what day of the week you thought of your theory The evidence for your theory is just as strong regardless of its timing

  44. Moral and inferential paradoxes of orthodoxy: 3. On the orthodox approach, you must correct for how many tests you conduct in total. For example, if you ran 100 correlations and 4 were just significant, researchers would not try to interpret those significant results. On Bayes, it does not matter how many other statistical hypotheses you investigated (or your RA without telling you). All that matters is the data relevant to each hypothesis under investigation.

  45. For orthodoxy but not Bayes: Different people with the same data and theories can come to different conclusions You can thus be tempted to make false (albeit inferentially irrelevant claims), like when you thought of your theory

More Related