1 / 22

CSE 105 theory of computation

CSE 105 theory of computation. Fall 2019 https://cseweb.ucsd.edu/classes/fa19/cse105-a/. Today's learning goals Sipser Ch 4.1, 4.2. Trace high-level descriptions of algorithms for computational problems.

jara
Télécharger la présentation

CSE 105 theory of computation

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. CSE 105 theory of computation Fall 2019 https://cseweb.ucsd.edu/classes/fa19/cse105-a/

  2. Today's learning goals Sipser Ch 4.1, 4.2 • Trace high-level descriptions of algorithms for computational problems. • Use counting arguments to prove the existence of unrecognizable (undecidable) languages. • Use diagonalization in a proof of undecidability.

  3. Undecidable? • There are many ways to prove that a problem is decidable. • How do we find (and prove) that a problem is notdecidable?

  4. Counting arguments Before we proved the Pumping Lemma … We proved there was a set that was not regular because Uncountable All sets of strings All Regular Sets Countable

  5. Counting arguments Uncountable All sets of strings Why is the set of Turing-recognizable languages countable? • It's equal to the set of all TMs, which we showed is countable. • It's a subset of the set of all TMs, which we showed is countable. • Each Turing-recognizable language is associated with a TM, so there can be no more Turing-recognizable languages than TMs. • More than one of the above. • I don't know. All Turing-recognizable sets Countable

  6. Satisfied? • Maybe not … • What's a specific example of a language that is not Turing-recognizable? or not Turing-decidable? • Idea: consider a set that, were it to be Turing-decidable, would have to "talk" about itself, and contradict itself!

  7. ATM Recall ADFA = {<B,w> | B is a DFA and w is in L(B) } Decider for this set simulates arbitrary DFA ATM = {<M,w> | M is a TM and w is in L(M) } Decider for this set simulates arbitrary TMs ???

  8. ATM ATM = {<M,w> | M is a TM and w is in L(M) } Define the TM N = "On input <M,w>: • Simulate M on w. • If M accepts, accept. If M rejects, reject."

  9. ATM ATM = {<M,w> | M is a TM and w is in L(M) } Define the TM N = "On input <M,w>: • Simulate M on w. • If M accepts, accept. If M rejects, reject." What is L(N)?

  10. ATM ATM = {<M,w> | M is a TM and w is in L(M) } Define the TM N = "On input <M,w>: • Simulate M on w. • If M accepts, accept. If M rejects, reject." Does N decide ATM?

  11. ATM ATM = {<M,w> | M is a TM and w is in L(M) } Define the TM N = "On input <M,w>: • Simulate M on w. • If M accepts, accept. If M rejects, reject." Conclude: ATM is Turing-recognizable. Is it decidable?

  12. Diagonalization proof: ATM not decidable Sipser 4.11 Assume, towards a contradiction, that it is. Call MATM the decider for ATM: For every TM M and every string w, • Computation of MATM on <M,w> halts and accepts if w is in L(M). • Computation of MATM on <M,w> halts and rejects if w is not in L(M). MATM ≠ N

  13. Diagonalization proof: ATM not decidable Sipser 4.11 Assume, towards a contradiction, that MATM decides ATM Define the TM D = "On input <M>: • Run MATM on <M, <M>>. • If MATM accepts, reject; if MATM rejects, accept."

  14. Diagonalization proof: ATM not decidable Sipser 4.11 Assume, towards a contradiction, that MATM decides ATM Define the TM D = "On input <M>: • Run MATM on <M, <M>>. • If MATM accepts, reject; if MATM rejects, accept." Which of the following computations halt? Computation of D on <X> Computation of D on <Y> where Y is TM with L(Y) =Σ* Computation of D on <D> All of the above.

  15. Diagonalization proof: ATM not decidable Sipser 4.11 Assume, towards a contradiction, that MATM decides ATM Define the TM D = "On input <M>: • Run MATM on <M, <M>>. • If MATM accepts, reject; if MATM rejects, accept." Consider running D on input <D>. Because D is a decider: • either computation halts and accepts … • or computation halts and rejects …

  16. Diagonalization proof: ATM not decidable Sipser 4.11 Diagonalization??? Self-reference "Is <D> an element of L(D)?" Assume, towards a contradiction, that MATM decides ATM Define the TM D = "On input <M>: • Run MATM on <M, <M>>. • If MATM accepts, reject; if MATM rejects, accept." Consider running D on input <D>. Because D is a decider: • either computation halts and accepts … • or computation halts and rejects …

  17. ATM • Recognizable • Not decidable Fact (from discussion section): A language is decidable iff it and its complement are both recgonizable. Corollary: The complement of ATM is unrecognizable.

  18. Decidable vs. undecidable Which of the following languages is undecidable? • INFINITEDFA = { <A> | A is a DFA and L(A) is an infinite language} • STM = { <M> | M is a TM and M has exactly 7 states} • RevDFA = { <B> | B is a DFA and for all strings w, B accepts w iff it accepts wR} • RecTM = { <X> | X is a TM and L(X) is recognizable} • DecTM = { <Y> | Y is a TM and L(Y) is decidable}

  19. So far

  20. Do we have to diagonalize? • Next time: comparing difficulty of problems.

More Related