1 / 22

Predicate Calculus 2

Predicate Calculus 2. Outline: Unification: definitions, algorithm Formal interpretations and satisfiability Horn clauses and PROLOG. Unification. Predicate calculus rules are sometimes so general that we need to create specializations of them in order to perform resolution.

merry
Télécharger la présentation

Predicate Calculus 2

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Predicate Calculus 2 Outline: Unification: definitions, algorithm Formal interpretations and satisfiability Horn clauses and PROLOG CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  2. Unification Predicate calculus rules are sometimes so general that we need to create specializations of them in order to perform resolution. Suppose we have the rule If x is a working automobile, then x has an engine. P(x)  Q(x) and we have the fact Tim’s Chevy is a working automobile P(a) These cannot immediately be resolved because P(x) and P(a) don’t quite match. They must be “unified.” CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  3. Modus Ponens and Resolution P  Q P --------- Q Modus ponens is a special case of resolution: P v Q P --------- Q CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  4. Modus Ponensin the Predicate Calculus P(a)  Q(a) P(a) --------- Q(a) But we have P(x)  Q(x) So we create a substitution instance of it: P(a)  Q(a) using the substitution { a/x } CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  5. Substitutions A substitution is a set of term/variable pairs. e.g., { a/x, f(a)/y, w/z } Each element of the set is an elementary substitution. A particular variable occurs at most once on the the right-hand side of any elementary subst. in a substitution. { a/x, b/x } is not an acceptable substitution. The empty set is an acceptable substitution. If E is a term or a formula of the predicate calculus, and S is a substitution, then S(E) is the result of applying S to E, i.e., replacing each variable of S that occurs in E by the corresponding term in S. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  6. Unifiers Given a pair of literals L1 and L2, if S is a substitution such that S(L1) = S(L2) or S(L1) = S(L2), then S is a unifier for L1 and L2. Example: L1 = P(x, f(a)) L2 = P(b, y) S = { b/x, f(a)/y } S(L1) = P(b, f(a)) = S(L2) Therefore S is a unifier for L1 and L2. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  7. The Occurs Check A unifier may not contain an elementary substitution of the form f(x)/x and may not cause an indefinite recursion. In general the term in a term/variable pair may not include that variable. P(x) and P(f(x)) cannot be unified, since f(x)/x is illegal. P(y, f(y)) and P(f(x), y) cannot be unified, since S = { f(x)/y, f(y)/x } leads to an indefinite recursion. Testing whether a variable appears in its corresponding term is called the “occurs check”. Some automated reasoning systems do not perform the occurs check in order to save time. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  8. Generality of Unifiers Some pairs of literals may have more than one possible unifier. P(x), P(y) is unified by each of { x/y }, { y/x }, { z/x, z/y }, { a/x, a/y}, { f(a)/x, f(a)/y } etc. Suppose S1 and S2 are unifiers for L1 and 12. Then S1(P1) = S1(P2) or S1(P1) = ~S1(P2) S2(P1) = S2(P2) or S2(P1) = ~S2(P2) S2 is less general than S1 if no S3 exists such that S3(S2(P1)) = S1(P1). { a/x, a/y } is less general than { y/x }. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  9. Most General Unifiers A unifier S1 for L1 and L2 is a most general unifier (MGU) for L1 and L2 provided that for any other unifier S2 of L1 and L2 there exists a substitution S3 such that S3(S1(L1)) = S2(L1). S1 = { y/x } is a most general unifier for P(x), P(y). S2 = { f(a)/x, f(a)/y } is not a MGU for P(x), P(y). S3 = { f(a)/y } S3(S1(P(x))) = P(f(a)) = S2(P(x)). CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  10. Finding a Most-General Unifier 1. Given literals L1 and L2, place a cursor at the left end of each. Skip any negation sign. If the predicate symbols do not match, return NOT-UNIFIABLE. 2. Let S = { }. 3. Move the cursors right to the next term in each literal. If there are no terms left, return S as a MGU. Let t1 and t2 be the terms. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  11. Finding an MGU (Cont.) 4a. If t1 = t2, go to Step 3. 4b. Otherwise, if either t1 or t2 is a variable (call it v and call the other term t), then attempt to add t/v to S (see below). 4c. Otherwise if t1 and t2 both begin with function symbols, and these symbols are the same, move the cursors to the first argument of these symbols and go to step 4a. 4d. Otherwise, return NOT-UNIFIABLE. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  12. Finding an MGU (Cont.) When trying to add t/v to S, apply { t/v } to each term in S. If this results in any elementary substitution whose term includes its variable, return NOT-UNIFIABLE. Otherwise, replace each elementary substitution in S by the result of applying { t/v } and add t/v itself to S. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  13. Example L1: P(a, f(x, a)) L2: P(a, f(g(y), y)) S: { } S: { g(y)/x } S: { g(a)/x, a/y } CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  14. Logical Inferences Per Second LIPS are sometimes used to describe the performance of a logical reasoning system. Can mean the number of successful unification operations per second. 1 successful unification  1 successful resolution step. Note: some unifiers are trivial to compute, yet there is no upper bound on the size of a unifier. Also, discovering that two literals are not unifiable can be arbitrarily costly. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  15. Formal Interpretations An interpretation for a given formula W consists of the following: A domain D of elements that can be referred to by terms. E.g., D = (0, 1, 2, . . . } An assignment that maps each constant symbol of W to an element of D. For each n-ary function symbol of W a mapping from n-tuples of elements of D to single elements of D. For each n-ary predicate symbol of W a mapping from n-tuples of elements of D to {T, F}. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  16. Example of Interpretation Let W =(x) (P(a)  Q(x, a) ) An interpretation for W: D = { apple, peach } { a = apple }mapping for constants { }mappings for functions { P(apple) = T, P(peach) = T;mappings for predicates Q(apple,apple) = T, Q(apple, peach) = T, Q(peach,apple) = T, Q(peach, peach) = T } CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  17. Satisfiability and Models A formula W is satisfiable iff there exists some interpretation of W that make W true. A formula W is unsatisfiable iff there does NOT exist any interpretation of W that make W true. Then W isinconsistent. W is a contradiction. If every interpretation of W satisfies W (makes W true), then W is a tautology. If I is an interpretation for W that satisfies W , then I is a model for W. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  18. Another Interpretation Let W = (x) (P(a)  Q(x, a) ) An interpretation for W: D = { 0, 1, 2, . . . } { a = 0 } mapping for constants { } mappings for functions { P(n) iff n = 0; mappings for predicates Q(m,n) iff n > m. } Note that Q(x, x). This interpretation fails to satisfy W. It’s not a model for W. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  19. The Basis of Proof by Resolution Resolution is used to prove that a given set of clauses is inconsistent. (i.e., it cannot have a model). Each time a resolvent is formed, it is added to the set of clauses. This does not change the consistency of the set. However, if the null clause is ever added to the set, then it becomes very obvious that the set is inconsistent. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  20. Horn Clauses: The basis for Logic Programming A Horn clause is a clause in which at most one literal is unnegated Examples of Horn clauses: P P V Q Q Q V R P V Q V R P V Q V R [] Examples of non-Horn clauses: P V Q P V ~Q V R CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  21. Horn Clauses: Goal-oriented form P V Q V R Standard mathematical form (Q  R) P Equivalent conditional form P  (Q V R) Goal-oriented form p :- q, r. Edinburgh PROLOG syntax head :- body. goal :- subgoal1, subgoal2, ..., subgoalN. CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

  22. Prolog: Horn Clauses + Resolution + Backward Chaining grandparent(X, Y) :- parent(X, Z), parent(Z, Y). parent(X, Y) :- father(X, Y). parent(X, Y) :- mother(X, Y). father(abe, bev). mother(bev, carl). mother(bev, mary). ?- grandmother(A, B). A = abe, B = carl; A = abe, B = mary; no CSE 415 -- (c) S. Tanimoto, 2008 Predicate Calculus II

More Related