1 / 18

Efficient Voting via the T op-k Elicitation Scheme: A Probabilistic Approach

Efficient Voting via the T op-k Elicitation Scheme: A Probabilistic Approach. Joel Oren, University of Toronto Joint work with Yuval Filmus , Institute of Advanced Study. Motivation. Common theme : communication-efficient group decision-making.

psyche
Télécharger la présentation

Efficient Voting via the T op-k Elicitation Scheme: A Probabilistic Approach

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Efficient Voting via the Top-k Elicitation Scheme: A Probabilistic Approach Joel Oren, University of Toronto Joint work with Yuval Filmus, Institute of Advanced Study

  2. Motivation • Common theme: communication-efficient group decision-making. • How to pick the single “best” item/candidate, without extracting too much information from the customers/committee members. • Hiring committees: members can’t rank all of the candidates. • Too many candidates. • Committee members may only be familiar with just subsets of candidates in their own fields.

  3. The Basic Setting • Candidates (alternatives/products): • Agents with preferences over the possible outcomes. A canonical task: select the “best” outcome. What is the information need for doing so. Social choice: methods for aggregating preferences. Efficient preference elicitation.

  4. Basic Definitions • – candidates, – set of all orderings over . • Voter set with preferences . • Voting rule: . • Score-based voting rules: assign each candidate a score, pick the one with maximal score (most voting rules). • Positional scoring rules (PSR):score vector , ’th ranked candidate receives a score of . • Question:do we really need to know all of to pick Harmonic Borda Geometric

  5. Top- Voting – The General Elicitation Scheme • Given a prescribed voting rule , ask each voter to report only his the length- prefix of her preferences. • Voter reports only . • The top- elicitation scheme: an algorithm that • Elicits • Computes a function that picks a winner `based on and the voting rule . • Question: how large does need to be so that ?

  6. Previous Work • Theoretically: many common voting rules require a lot of information from the voters, in the worst case [Conitzer & Sandholm’02,05, Xia & Conitzer’08]. • Top- voting: Complexity of finding possible/necessary winners [Baumeister et al.’12]. • Empirically: in practice, top- voting performs well [Kalech et al.’11]. • Bridging the gap: assume a distributional model of preferences. • Lu & Boutilier’11: studied the performance of partial preference elicitation for regret-minimization a objective, under distributional assumptions. • Recently: A lower-bound on , for selecting the Borda winner in an impartial culture [O, Filmus, Boutilier’13].

  7. A Distributional Approach to Top- Voting • Input: • Scoring rule: . Focus: positional scoring rules. • Top- algorithm :given top- votes, selects a winning candidate. • Each preference : drawn i.i.d. from distribution over . • Output:. Q: for which , , w.h.p.

  8. Three Distributional Models (and high-level Results) • Three distributional models (increasing order of hardness): • Biased Distributions: distributions that “favor” one particular candidate over all else. (positionally-biased, pairwise-biased). • Overall results: As , is sufficient for many scoring rules. See paper for details. • Impartial Culture: is the uniform distribution over . • Main results: • PSRs: an almost tight threshold theorem. • Additional scoring rule: Copeland. • Adversarial: is set by an adversary, but is fully known to us. • Main results: • Harmonic PSR: A worst-case distribution requiring . • Geometric PSR: for any – sufficient; this is tight.

  9. Top- for PSRs: under an Impartial Culture • Goal: Given a score vector , s.t., determine a LB and an UB in the limit. • Possible algorithms the upper bound: • OPT alg.: compute the winning prob. of candidates – not clear how to rigorously analyze such an algorithm. • Naïve: ∀, , if , , otherwise. • FairCutOff: like Naïve, but if , .

  10. Empirical Results for the three algorithms • , sample populations. FairCutoff overlaps with Opt FairCutoff overlaps with Opt Borda Harmonic

  11. A Threshold Theorem for PSRs • The top- scores according to FairCutoff: for , • We consider a measure depending on the amount of “noise” in each of the two parts of the score vector, in terms of : • , • Set – the -partition variability ratio. • Theorem: in the limit • LB: if , no top- can determine the right winner w.p. . • UB: if , then FairCutoff determines the right winner w.p. .

  12. Applications Theorem: in the limit • LB: if , no top- can determine the right winner w.p. . • UB: if , then FairCutoff determines the right winner w.p. . • Borda: assuming that , . Gives a LB of (improvement over the previous bound of ). • Harmonic: UB – is sufficient,LB – . • Geometric: () UB – -- sufficient,LB – .

  13. Proof Sketch – Order Statistics of Correlated RVs • Upper bound: FairCutoff guesses the right winner w.h.p. • For each candidate, partition voter scores based on top-/bottom-( partition: + + + + + + + + +

  14. Proof Sketch (continued) • Each candidate’s score is the sum: . • Score according to top-. • First and second order statistics: . • First step: estimate the distribution of . • Complication: the scores are correlated – diagonalize covariance matrix via a linear transformation, without affecting the distribution of the difference. • Approximate via CLT + order statistics analysis of Gaussian RVs. • Difference grows as variance of grows (). • Second step: switch from to loses the “added noise” – has a bounded effect (use – above gap won’t be closed, w.h.p.

  15. Top- elicitation under Copleland’s rule • The scoring rule: for every two distinct candidates , set( if beats [loses to] in a pairwise election. If there’s a tie, set . • A candidate’s score is: . • Theorem: for , no top- algorithm predicts the correct winner w.p. ().

  16. The Adversarial Model • The preference distribution is set by an adversary – the full specifications are given to the decision maker. • How bad can the bounds be for that case? • Borda: already got a lower bound of . • Harmonic: we have a polylog UB for the impartial culture. • Theorem: For a fixed , there is a distribution , such that any top- algorithm requires , under the harmonic scoring rule. • Geometric: a UB under an impartial culture. • Theorem: if the decay factor is fixed, then issufficient under the geometric scoring rule, under any distribution, and this is tight.

  17. Conclusions & Future Directions • A rigorous, probabilistic analysis of the top- elicitation scheme. • Under impartial culture: a principled method of analysis with applications: • Result for Copeland: extension to weighted majority graph based rules? • Can we extend our results to other rules? • More involved distributions: mixture models. • Top-k for proportional representation.

  18. Contact:oren@cs.toronto.eduHomepage: www.cs.toronto.edu/~oren Thank you!

More Related