1 / 25

Justice in Action: Just War Theory

Justice in Action: Just War Theory. Ethics Matters. The origins of just war theory. Just war theory has a long and finely-textured tradition, going back to St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas.

devin
Télécharger la présentation

Justice in Action: Just War Theory

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Justice in Action:Just War Theory Ethics Matters (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  2. The origins of just war theory Just war theory has a long and finely-textured tradition, going back to St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas. The most influential theorist of just war during the last fifty years has been Michael Walzer, whose Just and Unjust Wars is the key work. © Lawrence M. Hinman

  3. Just war theory today • The discussion of just war theory remains a crucial topic today, including in our nation’s military academies and war colleges. • It is not uncommon to see military officers participating in scholarly conferences on just war theories and its challenges. (The CIA is rarely a participant.) • The International Society for Military Ethics (formerly JSCOPE) is a key venue for these discussions. © Lawrence M. Hiinman

  4. Overview Three principal areas: • The just conditions for entering into a war. • When is it just to go to war? • The just conditions for conducting a war. • What are we permitted to do in carrying out a war and what is forbidden as unjust? • The just conditions of peace. • What are the conditions of peace that insure the just conclusion of a war? (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  5. Part One: Jus ad bellum:The Just Conditions for Going to War Just war theorists typically recognize six conditions that must be met before a country is morally justified in going to war: • Just cause • Right intention • Proper authority and public declaration • Last resort • Probability of success • Proportionality (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  6. Just cause Just war theorists typically acknowledge two conditions under which then entry into war is justified: • Protection from external attack is the first and foremost—and in the eyes of some, the only--just cause of war; based on the right of self-defense. • Some have maintained the humanitarian intervention is also justified, where we go to war to save the lives of innocent people who are being attacked by an aggressor. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  7. Right intention • The war must be pursued for a just cause. • Unacceptable intentions: • Revenge • Political expansion • Land acquisition (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  8. Proper authority and public declaration • Traditionally, only nations have the authority to declare war. • Wars must be publicly declared, not pursued in secret. • Question: Can terrorist groups be said to declare war? If not, is the response to terrorism really war? (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  9. Last resort • If there are other means of achieving the same objectives, such as negotiations or economic blockades, they should be pursued exhaustively first. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  10. Probability of success • The rationale here is clear and simple: war is a great evil, and it is wrong to cause such killing, suffering, and destruction in a futile effort. • Question: what about countries that feel they are resisting evil even when there is little or no chance of success? For example, small European countries being invaded by the Nazis. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  11. Proportionality • Are the possible benefits (especially in terms of a just peace) proportional to the death, suffering, and destruction that the pursuit of the war will bring about? (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  12. Part Two. Jus in bello:The Just Conditions for Conducting a War Three principal conditions must commonly be met in the conduct of war: • Discrimination • Proportionality • No means that are evil in themselves. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  13. Discrimination • The key requirement here is to discriminate between those who are engaged in harm (soldiers) and those who are not (civilians). • This has increasingly become an issue in the last fifty years when there are no clear battle lines and when one side often does not wear a uniform. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  14. Proportionality • One should only use the amount of force that is proportional to the (just) ends being sought. • This raises important questions about the massive use of force in many conflicts: • The Nazi attack on the Spanish village of Guernica was immortalized in Pablo Picasso’s painting. • As the means of war became more powerful, we have had more and more examples of such excessive use of force. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  15. Guernica:The lack of proportionality

  16. No Means Evil in Themselves • Orend lists a number of means that count as evil in themselves. • Mass rape campaigns as an instrument of war; • Child soldiers; • Genocide or ethnic cleansing; • Torturing captured enemy soldiers; • Using weapons whose effects cannot be controlled, such as chemical or biological agents or nuclear weapons. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  17. Part Three. Jus post bellum:Creating a Just Peace The purpose of war is to achieve a just and lasting peace. Without such a peace, we are simply condemned to a series of repetitive wars. The vision of a just peace ought to guide both the decision to go to war and the conduct of the war. • Contrast Sherman’s march through Georgia with Lincoln’s treatment of Confederate soldiers. • Contrast WWI and WWII and their respective peace treaties. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  18. Five Conditions of a Just Peace There are five conditions necessary for a just peace: • Just cause for termination • Right intention • Public declaration and legitimate authority • Discrimination • Proportionality (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  19. Just cause for termination • Orend: “a reasonable vindication of those rights whose violation grounded the resort to war in the first place.” • Unjust gains from aggression have been eliminated • Victims’ rights reinstated • Formal apology • Acceptance of reasonable punishment (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  20. Right intention • Excludes motives such as revenge • Prosecution of war crimes needs to be applied to all, not just the vanquished. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  21. Public declaration and legitimate authority • This requirement is fairly straightforward and uncontroversial. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  22. Discrimination • Differentiate between • Political and military leaders • Military and civilian populations • Punish the elite responsible for prosecuting the war, not the uninvolved civilians. (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  23. Proportionality • The vanquished do not lose their rights • No ‘witch hunts’ • Proportional to reasonable rights vindication (c) Lawrence M. Hinman

  24. War in the 20th Century Much of traditional just war theory rests on the assumption of: • A conflict between two nation state (such as a war between France and Germany) • Clearly drawn battle linesand fronts with uniformed armies that can be clearly identified.

  25. War in the 21st Century In the 21st century, we see new paradigms for warfare emerging that no longer fit well into the traditional categories of just war theory: • Insurgency and counterinsurgency • Increasing role of CIA and other agencies instead of the military • Drones and robotic warfare • Cyber warfare • Economic sanctions and currency warfare

More Related