1 / 36

Reason and Argument

Reason and Argument. Chapter 6 (1/4). Common misperceptions about logic:. “…The science of Deduction and Analysis is one which can only be acquired by long and patient study, nor is life long enough to allow any mortal to attain the highest possible perfection in it.” From A Study in Scarlet.

ehren
Télécharger la présentation

Reason and Argument

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Reason and Argument Chapter 6 (1/4)

  2. Common misperceptions about logic: • “…The science of Deduction and Analysis is one which can only be acquired by long and patient study, nor is life long enough to allow any mortal to attain the highest possible perfection in it.” From A Study in Scarlet

  3. A joke: Sherlock Holmes and Dr. Watson go on a camping trip. After a good dinner and a bottle of wine, they retire for the night, and go to sleep. Some hours later, Holmes wakes up and nudges his faithful friend. "Watson, look up at the sky and tell me what you see.""I see millions and millions of stars, Holmes" replies Watson."And what do you deduce from that?"Watson ponders for a minute."Well, astronomically, it tells me that there are millions of galaxies and potentially billions of planets. Astrologically, I observe that Saturn is in Leo. Horologically, I deduce that the time is approximately a quarter past three. Meteorologically, I suspect that we will have a beautiful day tomorrow. Theologically, I can see that God is all powerful, and that we are a small and insignificant part of the universe. What does it tell you, Holmes?" Holmes is silent for a moment.

  4. The punchline: "Watson, you idiot!" he says. "Someone has stolen our tent!"

  5. Common misperceptions about logic: • Typically, Spock said nothing about logic, per se. • Whenever Spock would claim that something was or was not logical, he generally meant ‘rational’.

  6. A note about the rules of logic: • The rules of logic are not made up or stipulated, or even proved (though they can be derived from one another like the axioms of Euclidian geometry, and as with any axiomatic system, at least one axiom will always remain unproven) • The rules of logic are discovered, and are lent force by the very fact that they’re obvious, otherwise we wouldn’t be able to call them rules of logic. • We’ll start with the simplest rules: the rules for ‘and’

  7. But first, Propositions: The textbook authors are (understandably) imprecise about talk of propositions. To wit: ‘John is Tall’ is not a proposition, just like ‘3’ is not a number.

  8. Propositions • ‘John is tall’ is a sentence that expresses the proposition that John is tall. • ‘3’ is a numeral that expresses what we mean by the number 3. • This is important because one should not get the idea that any sentence can express a proposition. To express a proposition, a sentence must be an example of a linguistic act.

  9. Propositional Form and Substitution Instances • p & q represents any two joined propositions. • Though the rule in the book (p. 144) allows that different variables be replaced by the same proposition, for practical purposes we will never do this. • Also contrary to the text, “Roses are red and violets are blue” does not represent a single proposition, but instead a conjunction of two of them. • The 8th edition of the book inserts a justification for this based on an analogy to mathematics. My reply: logic, whatever it looks like, is not precisely math. We have good reasons to limit one proposition to one propositional variable and vice versa.

  10. Something else about propositions: • Propositions are bearers of truth-values. • That means that any given proposition can have the property of being true or the property of being false, and all propositions have one or the other (which is why we insist on the linguistic act constraint) • Does that mean that we must view truth as a black-and-white kind of thing? Well, yes, it does.

  11. Got a problem with black and white? Why don’t you tell me that to my face! Thought so…

  12. Bearers of truth-value • Since propositions are expressed by sentences that are meaningful, they reflect states of affairs. In other words, they reflect the way things are or are not. • Take the proposition expressed by the sentence ‘John is tall’. • The proposition is true if it is considered in a state of affairs in which John is tall and it is false if it is considered in a state of affairs in which John is not tall. • Notice that whether we agree about the state of affairs is a different question.

  13. How truth tables work: • The leftmost columns are called reference columns and contain each individual propositional variable (or sentence), usually in alphabetical order. • There is one remaining column for each connective (&, v, ~, →) used. • Each row of a truth table corresponds to one possible state of affairs. • Every possible state of affairs is represented on a truth table. The number of rows is 2n where n is the number of reference columns.

  14. The truth table for ‘&’

  15. Propositional versus nonpropositional conjunction: • Exercise IV: • 1. nonpropositional • 2. nonpropositional • 3. nonpropositional • 4. propositional • 5. propositional • 6. nonpropositional • 7. nonpropositional • 8. either (ambiguous) • 9. nonpropositional

  16. Validity for ‘&’

  17. How about this one?

  18. What about this?

  19. Notice:

  20. How about:

  21. So any substitution instances of the following will ALWAYS be valid. p & q p p & q q p q___ p & q

  22. Exercise V • 1. valid • 2. not valid • 3. valid (trivially) • 4. valid • 5. valid (though conversationally, a different meaning is implied) • 6. nonpropositional, but valid (would require predicate logic to demonstrate)

  23. Exercise VI • 1. True • 2. True • 3. True

  24. Exclusive vs. Inclusive ‘or’ • Sometimes when a person says something of the form “p or q” they mean “p or q or both” and sometimes they mean “p or q and not both”. The former is an inclusive ‘or’ and the latter is exclusive. • Most logicians default to the inclusive ‘or’. Some even claim that all uses of ‘or’ are inclusive, and it is conversational implication that makes some of them exclusive. • In any case, it is important to examine cases where ‘or’ is used to determine which is which, because it will affect the validity of any argument that ‘or’ is used in.

  25. Disjunction

  26. Negation • It is tempting to say that “Smurfs are blue” and “Smurfs are not blue” are sentences that express two propositions. • That is not the case. What is going on is that the same proposition is involved, and in one case the proposition is negated. • If ‘s’ stands for “Smurfs are blue” and ‘~’ is our symbol for negation, then “Smurfs are not blue” is formalized as “~s”.

  27. Be careful with Negation • Sometimes ‘not’ is syntactically ambiguous. Translating ‘~’ as “it is not the case that…” can help to disentangle ambiguity. • Be careful with opposites. • “nobody owns Mars” is the negation of “somebody owns Mars” because “it is not the case that somebody owns Mars” means the same thing as “nobody owns Mars” • However, some opposites are not binary. Consider “Cheering for the Yankees is moral”. The negation of this should just be “It is not the case that cheering for the Yankees is moral”. Resist the temptation to translate the negation as “Cheering for the Yankees is immoral”. This is because actions that are not moral could be either amoral or immoral (but not both). • The point is, just be strict in translating ‘~’ as “it is not the case that…”

  28. Further ambiguity in negation: • Consider ~(Everyone loves running) • Not everyone loves running • Everyone does not love running • Everyone loves not running • No one loves running • Everyone hates running • Everyone loves walking • For the sake of Pete, just say “It is not the case that everyone loves running”

  29. Disjunctive Syllogism • Consider the argument: p v q ~p q

  30. Disjunctive Syllogism • Consider the argument: p v q ~p q VALID

  31. Consider the Argument: p v q p___ ~q

  32. Consider the Argument: p v q p___ ~q INVALID

  33. Pay attention to parentheses • Notice that ~a & g means something different than ~(a & g). • Substitute “Annie is rich” for ‘a’ and “Gina is happy” for ‘g’. • The first phrase translates to “It is not the case that Annie is rich and it is the case that Gina is happy.” • The second phrase translates to “It is not the case that both Annie is rich and Gina is happy.” • How about ~a & ~g?

  34. Logic and Math • I know that logic LOOKS for all the world like math, but resist the temptation to treat mathematical symbols and logical symbols as interchangeable. • For example, math has parentheses, and also has a negative symbol, “-” that looks a bit like logic’s negation symbol “~”, so since changing –(2 + 3) to -2 + -3 is a mathematically valid procedure, changing ~(p & q) to ~p & ~q should be logically valid, right?

  35. Equivalence of ~a & g, ~(a & g), ~a & ~g

  36. Exercise XII 15. A v ((~B & C) v ~(~B v ~(Z v B))) T v ((~T & T) v ~(~T v ~(F v T))) T v ((~T & T) v ~(~T v ~T)) T v ((~T & T) v ~(~T v ~T)) T v ((F & T) v ~(F v F)) T v ((F & T) v ~(F v F)) T v (F v ~F) T v (F v ~F) T v (F v T) T v (F v T) T v T T v T T

More Related