1 / 31

Utility central in economics.

Using Modern Nonexpected Utility Theories for Risky Decisions and Modern Tools from Experimental Economics to Revisit Classical Debates in Economics, and to Restore the Classical Utility Concept.

esparzal
Télécharger la présentation

Utility central in economics.

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Using Modern Nonexpected Utility Theories for Risky Decisions and Modern Tools from Experimental Economics to Revisit Classical Debates in Economics, and to Restore the Classical Utility Concept Peter P. Wakker; Erasmus University Rotterdam(& Abdellaoui & Barrios; Ecole Normale Supérieure of Cachan) Utility central in economics. - We review history and classical debates ("ordinal revolution"). - We bring novelty, using modern nonexpected utility and modern experimental economics, rather than philosophy & armchair speculation. Motto: "don't talk but look".

  2. 2 Our purpose: Show that choiceless inputs can be useful in economics; revival of old cardinal utility … Many others have pleaded for it in the past and in the present. Special aspect of our plea: Not ad hoc. Not just going back to Bentham. Rather: Link choiceless inputs to revealed preference. Build on,reinforce, revealed preference.Don't abandon it.

  3. 3 1. History of Utility 18th century • 1st appearance of utility:Cramer (1728), Bernoulli (1738) • 1st thorough analysis:Bentham (1789); Utility “intuitive.”

  4. 4 19th century Samuelson (1947, p. 206), about such views: "To a man like Edgeworth, steeped as he was in the Utilitarian tradition, individual utility—nay social utility—was as real as his morning jam." • Utility still intuitive  1870: the marginal revolution (Jevons 1871, Menger 1871, Walras 1874) Resolved Smith's (1776) paradox of value-in-use versus value-in-exchange (e.g. the "water-diamond" paradox).

  5. “Utility” is the heritage of Bentham and his theory of pleasures and pains. For us his word is the more acceptable, the less it is entangled with his theory. [Italics from original( Sect14, Chapter 1)] 5 1st half of 20th century Logical positivism: everything falsifiable. No metaphysics. In psychology: behaviorism. In economics: • Ordinal revolution:Pareto (1906), Hicks & Allen (1934) • Utility  choice. al direct judgment abandonedBaumol 1958, Fisher 1892, Pareto 1906, Slutsky 1915 U ordinal in mathe-matical sense

  6. 6 • von Neumann-Morgenstern (1944) with expected-utility for risky decisions, and utility cardinal in mathematical sense: • New hope for cardinality in empirical sense? • General consensus: Cardinal in mathematical sense, not empirical neoclassical; vNM-U only for risk; not for welfare evaluations etc. • Cardinal utility exists in subfields(risky, welfare, taxation, temporal)but strictly kept there. • Ordinal view dominates.(So, no meaning for utility differences.)

  7. 7 First there were positive results and hope for ordinalism: • Hicks & Allen (1934): Market phenomena only need ordinal utility. • Samuelson (1938), Houthakker (1950): Preference revealed from market demand. • de Finetti (1937), Savage (1954): Choice-basis of subjective beliefs. • Debreu (1959): Existence of market equilibrium.

  8. 8 History of utility after 1950: No account of it known to us. There are several accounts of history up to and including ordinal revolution (Stigler 1950, Blaug 1962 & 1997). Yet, many changes occurred since 1950. Time for an update!

  9. History of utility after 1950: Allais (1953) & Ellsberg (1961): > < EU 9 First-generation models didn't yet question ordinal position: nonEU. However … Arrow (1951): No good social procedure when only ordinal information. Simon (1955): Bounded rationality; satisficing. Most serious blow for ordinalism: Preference reversals (Lichtenstein & Slovic '71, Grether & Plott '79).

  10. 10 A new, recent, blow. Kahneman (1994, & al.) for intertemporal choice. Big irrationalities: People seemingly prefer prolongation of pain. Shows that: Often, human species cannot integrate over time. Then: No revealed preference. Better resort (back) to Bentham's "experienced utility."

  11. 11 Typical Questions for cardinal utility (not discussed here): • Is utility - a property of the commodity? - a property of the consumer? • - ultimate index of goodness? • index for other good things • (expected offspring …). • Is utility • If child reveals clear preference for candy over medicine, then how about utility thereof? • If two persons have different utilities, must it be due to different background/circumstances of an objective kind?

  12. 12 Experimental Economics and Utility; Plan of Paper For answering the questions:"Do cardinal and/or ordinal utility exist?""Are they the same?" experimental economics' approach is: (Try to) measure them, and see! No philosophical contemplations here. A table organizing some utility-related phenomena, and positioning our contribution:

  13. 13 Market equilibria Risk Experienced (Kahneman) Welfare Strength of preferences happiness Intertemporal : Relation obtained in this paper. choice-based choiceless ordinal utility cardinal utility Utilities within rectangles are commonly restricted to their domains. Mark Machina, Jun'02: “The word utility has too many meanings. I avoid using the word utility.” We: not more concepts, but fewer. Relate them.

  14. 14 3. Plan of paper First, measure utility through risky decisions(choice-based). - Empirical problems for traditional EU; have frustrated utility measurements. - Can be fixed using prospect theory (Bleichrodt, Pinto, & Wakker 2001, Management Science). Next, measure utility through strength of preference; direct judgments (choiceless). Finally, compare these utilities.

  15. 15 4. The Experiment 1st utility measurement: Tradeoff (TO) method (Wakker & Deneffe 1996) Completely choice-based.

  16. t1 200,000   ~     _ _ 2/3 2/3 (U(2000)-U(1000)) (U(2000)-U(1000))  ~  2000 2000 1000 1000 1/3 1/3 ~ =   . . .   = 18, 1 curve 16 Tradeoff (TO) method (U(t1)-U(t0)) = (U(2000) - U(1000)) U(1000) + U(t1) = U(2000) + U(t0); EU 2000 1000 _ 2/3 U(t1)-U(t0)= (U(2000)-U(1000))  1/3 6,000 5000 (=t0) = U(t2)-U(t1)= t1 t2 . . . U(t6)-U(t5)= t5 t6

  17. t1 200,000 EU   2000 1000 _ d1 d1 d1 2/3 U(t1)-U(t0)= (U(2000)-U(1000))  ~ 1/3 12,000 5000   (=t0) = ! ?   _ _ 2/3 2/3 (U(2000)-U(1000)) (U(2000)-U(1000)) U(t2)-U(t1)= ~   2000 2000 1000 1000 d2 d2 d2 1/3 1/3 ~ t1 t2 = ? !   . . . . . .   = ! ? U(t6)-U(t5)= t5 t6 21, curves; then 23, CE1/3 17 Tradeoff (TO) method Prospect theory: weighted probs (even unknown probs)

  18. 1 U 5/6 4/6 3/6 2/6 1/6 0 t3 t4 t5 $ Consequently:U(tj) = j/6. 18 Normalize:U(t0) = 0; U(t6) = 1. t1 t2 t0 t6

  19. Based on direct judgment, not choice-based. 19 2nd utility measurement: Strength of Preference (SP)

  20. 20 Strength of Preference (SP) We assume: For which s2 is ? s2 t1 t1t0 U(s2) – U(t1) = U(t1) – U(t0) ~* For which s3 is ? s3 s2 t1t0 U(s3) – U(s2) = U(t1) – U(t0) ~* . . . . . . For which s6 is s6s5 ~* t1t0? U(s6) – U(s5) = U(t1) – U(t0)

  21. CE2/3(PT) SP CE2/3(EU) CE1/3 TO t0= FF5,000 t6= FF26,068 26, which th? PT! (then TO)) 23, CE1/3 25, CE2/3 22, nonTO ,nonEU 24, power? 28,concl 21 7/6 1 U 5/6 4/6 3/6 2/6 1/6 0 FF Utility functions (group averages) TO(PT) = TO(EU) CE1/3(PT) = CE1/3 (EU) (gr.av.) CE2/3(PT) corrects CE2/3 (EU)

  22. 22 Question: Could this identity have resulted becausethe TO method does not properly measurechoice-based risky utility? (And, after answering this, what about nonEU?)

  23.   For which c2:    ? t0 c1 For which c1: ~ ? c2 c2 c3 For which c3: ~ ? t6 21, curves 21, curves 23 3d utility measurement: Certainty equivalent CE1/3 (with good-outcome probability 1/3) EU & RDU & PT (for gr.av.) t0 c2 U(c2) = 1/3 ~ (Chris Starmer, June 24, 2005) on inverse-S: "It is not universal. But if I had to bet, I would bet on this one.". t6 U(c1) = 1/9 U(c3) = 5/9

  24. 24 • Questions • Could this identity have resulted because our experiment is noisy(cannot distinguish anything)? • How about violations of EU?

  25. For which d2: ?   d1 For which d1: ~ ?   d3 For which d3: ~ ?  21, curves 21, curves 25 4th utility measurement: 2/3 Certainty equivalent CE (with good-outcome probability 2/3) CE2/3(EU): CE2/3(PT) (gr.av): t0 d2 U(d2) = 2/3 U(d2) = .51 ~ t6 t0 U(d1) = 4/9 U(d1) = .26 d2 d2 U(d3) = 8/9 U(d3) = .76 t6

  26. 26 So, our experiment does have the statistical power to distinguish. And, EU is violated. Which alternative theory to use? Prospect theory.

  27. .51 1/3 2/3 16,TOmethod 27 1 w 1 0 1/3 p Fig.The common probability weighting function. w(1/3) = 1/3; w(2/3) = .51 We re-analyze the preceding measurements(the curves you saw before) in terms of prospect theory; first TO.

  28. Underone risky utility, UCE2/3= UCE1/3 = UTO = USP However: RDU : PT 28 5. Conclusions Under EU:usual discrepancies for risky ut., UCE2/3 UCE1/3 , UTO Risky choice-based U = riskless choiceless U??

  29. Interest in choiceless inputs in economics: 29 • Fox, Craig R. & Amos Tversky (1998), "A Belief-Based Account of Decision under Uncertainty," Management Science 44, 879895. • Gilboa & Schmeidler (2001), "A Cognitive Model of Individual Well-Being," Social Choice and Welfare 18, 269–288. • Kahneman (1994), "New Challenges to the Rationality Assumption," Journal of Instit. & Theor. Ecs 150,18-36. • Ladyard (2005), "Happiness, Lessons from a New Science." Penguin, London. • Tinbergen, Jan (1991), “On the Measurement of Welfare,” Journal of Econometrics 50, 713. • van Praag, Bernard M.S. (1968), "Individual Welfare Functions and Consumer Behavior.” North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1968. Especially useful if choice anomalies are prominent. We: relate choiceless inputs to revealed preference. Show how choiceless inputs can reinforcerevealed preference!

  30. 30 Experimental economics has shed new light on classical debates about utility: Don't talk but look.

  31. 31 Appendix on Analysis of Data All analyses with ANOVA (so, correcting for individual variation). We tested on raw data, and on parametric fittings. Parametric fittings of utility of: Power (CRRA); Exponential (CARA); We developed a one-parametric subfamily of Saha's expo-power satisfying economic desiderata; first presented in ESA-Amsterdam, October 2000. Later used by Holt & Laury (2002).

More Related