1 / 68

Chapter Thirty-Three

Chapter Thirty-Three. Law and Economics. Effects of Laws. Property right assignments affect asset, income and wealth distributions; e.g. nationalized vs. privately owned industry. Effects of Laws. Property right assignments affect asset, income and wealth distributions;

essien
Télécharger la présentation

Chapter Thirty-Three

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Chapter Thirty-Three Law and Economics

  2. Effects of Laws • Property right assignments affect • asset, income and wealth distributions; • e.g. nationalized vs. privately owned industry.

  3. Effects of Laws • Property right assignments affect • asset, income and wealth distributions; • e.g. nationalized vs. privately owned industry. • resource allocations; • e.g. the tragedy of the commons • e.g. patents encourage research.

  4. Effects of Laws • Punishments affect • incentives for illegal behavior; • e.g. high speeding fines can reduce the amount of speeding.

  5. Effects of Laws • Punishments affect • incentives for illegal behavior; • e.g. high speeding fines can reduce the amount of speeding. • asset, income and wealth distributions; • e.g. jail time results in lost income.

  6. Crime and Punishment • x is the quantity of an illegal activity produced by an individual. • C(x) is the production cost. • B(x) is the benefit. • Gain is B(x) - C(x). • What is the rational choice of x?

  7. Crime and Punishment First-order condition is Notice that marginal costs matter more than do total costs.

  8. Crime and Punishment B(x) C(x), low MC

  9. Crime and Punishment B(x) C(x), higher, but same MC C(x), low MC No change to illegal activity level.

  10. Crime and Punishment B(x) C(x), low MC

  11. Crime and Punishment B(x) C(x), high MC C(x), low MC Higher marginal costs deter crime.

  12. Crime and Punishment • Detection of a criminal is uncertain. • e is police effort. • (e) is detection probability; (e) = 0 if e = 0 (e)  as e .

  13. Crime and Punishment • Given e, the criminal’s problem is

  14. Crime and Punishment • Given e, the criminal’s problem is • First-order condition is

  15. Crime and Punishment • Given e, the criminal’s problem is • First-order condition is • Low e  low (e)  low marg. cost. • High e  high (e)  high marg. cost.

  16. Crime and Punishment B(x) Higher police effort deters crime.

  17. Crime and Punishment • Higher fines and larger police effort both raise marginal production costs of illegal activity. • Which is better for society -- higher fines, or more police effort?

  18. Crime and Punishment • Higher fines and larger police effort both raise marginal production costs of illegal activity. • Which is better for society -- higher fines, or more police effort? • Police effort consumes resources; higher fines do not. • Better to fine heavily.

  19. Liability Law • An injurer, IN, and a victim, V. • x is effort by IN to avoid injuring V. • cIN(x) is IN’s cost of effort x; cIN(x)  as x . • L(x) is V’s loss when IN’s effort is x; L(x)  as x .

  20. Liability Law • Society wishes to minimize total cost; i.e.

  21. Liability Law • Society wishes to minimize total cost; i.e. • Social optimality requires • I.e. IN’s private marginal cost of effort equals marginal benefit of her extra effort.

  22. Liability Law • Liability rules: • no liability rule • strict liability rule • negligence rule. • Which is best?

  23. Liability Law • No Liability Rule: • IN faces only private cost, cIN(x). • Hence chooses effort level • No liability results in suboptimal low care level and excessive injury.

  24. Liability Law • Full Liability Rule: • IN faces private cost and V’s costs, cIN(x) + L(x). • Hence chooses the socially optimal effort level where

  25. Liability Law • Negligence Rule: IN is liable for V’s loss if and only if care effort level , a legally determined effort level.

  26. Liability Law • Negligence Rule: IN is liable for V’s loss if and only if care effort level , a legally determined effort level. • What if the court sets , the socially optimal effort level?

  27. Liability Law • So  full liability for IN; hence she chooses

  28. Liability Law • So  full liability for IN; hence she chooses • And  no liability for IN; hence she chooses

  29. Liability Law • So  full liability for IN; hence she chooses • And  no liability for IN; hence she chooses • I.e. the negligence rule is socially optimal when

  30. Liability Law • Both full liability and negligence rules are socially optimal, but • full liability fully insures V always, and • the negligence rule fully insures V only if IN’s care effort level .

  31. Liability Law • Both full liability and negligence rules are socially optimal, but • full liability fully insures V always, and • the negligence rule fully insures V only if IN’s care effort level . • Victims prefer full liability; injurers prefer the negligence rule.

  32. Bilateral Accidents • V and IN can each exert effort to avoid a loss. • cV(xV) and cIN(xIN). • Loss is L(xV,xIN). • Society wishes to

  33. Bilateral Accidents • Society wishes to • Social optimality requires V’s MC of effort = MB of his effort IN’s MC of effort = MB of her effort. • I.e.

  34. Bilateral Accidents • No Liability: Both V and IN face only their private effort costs, not the full social costs of their actions.

  35. Bilateral Accidents • No Liability: Both V and IN face only their private effort costs, not the full social costs of their actions. • Hence V and IN both provide too little effort. • No liability is socially suboptimal.

  36. Bilateral Accidents • Full Liability: V is fully compensated for all injury costs.

  37. Bilateral Accidents • Full Liability: V is fully compensated for all injury costs. • Hence V chooses • Full liability is socially suboptimal in bilateral accidents.

  38. Bilateral Accidents • Strict Division of Losses: IN must pay a fixed fraction, f, of loss caused. • IN minimizes • IN chooses effort satisfying

  39. Bilateral Accidents • IN chooses effort satisfying • Optimality requires • Since f < 1, IN chooses less than the optimal effort level;

  40. Bilateral Accidents • IN chooses effort satisfying • Optimality requires • Since f < 1, IN chooses less than the optimal effort level; • Strict division of losses is a socially suboptimal liability rule.

  41. Bilateral Accidents • Negligence Rule: IN is fully liable for loss only if her effort level , a legally determined effort level. • Social optimality requires V and IN to choose effort levels and , where and

  42. Bilateral Accidents • Suppose V chooses • Then IN is fully liable and wishes to • I.e. IN chooses

  43. Bilateral Accidents • Now suppose IN chooses • Then V wishes to • I.e. V chooses

  44. Bilateral Accidents • Now suppose IN chooses • Then V wishes to • I.e. V chooses • The Nash equilibrium of the negligence rule game is the socially optimal outcome.

  45. Bilateral Accidents • Strict Liability with Defense of Contributory Negligence Rule: IN is fully liable unless V’s care level is less than a specified level

  46. Bilateral Accidents • IN is fully liable unless V’s care level is less than a specified level • If society chooses and V chooses , then IN is fully liable, so her best reply is

  47. Bilateral Accidents • IN is fully liable unless V’s care level is less than a specified level • If society chooses and V chooses , then IN is fully liable, so her best reply is • If IN chooses , then V’s best reply is

  48. Bilateral Accidents • IN is fully liable unless V’s care level is less than a specified level • If society chooses and V chooses , then IN is fully liable, so her best reply is • If IN chooses , then V’s best reply is • I.e. the rule causes a socially optimal Nash equilibrium.

  49. Bilateral Accidents • Notes: • socially optimal liability rules do not generally fully compensate the victim. • socially optimal accident deterrence is distinct from optimal accident compensation.

  50. Treble Damages & Antitrust Law • The Sherman and Clayton Acts allow an agent damaged by price-fixing to sue and recover treble damages. • How does such a penalty affect the behavior of a price-fixing cartel?

More Related