1 / 26

The Brain as a Hierarchical Organization

The Brain as a Hierarchical Organization. Isabelle Brocas USC and CEPR. Juan D. Carrillo USC and CEPR. March 2006. Evidence from Neuroscience: which brain system is activated when. Modeling techniques of Micro theory: agency & incentive theory, organizational design, etc.

yauvani
Télécharger la présentation

The Brain as a Hierarchical Organization

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. The Brain as a Hierarchical Organization Isabelle BrocasUSC and CEPR Juan D. CarrilloUSC and CEPR March 2006

  2. Evidence from Neuroscience:which brain system is activated when Modeling techniques of Micro theory:agency & incentive theory,organizational design, etc. The brain is and should be modeled as a multi-agent organization What is “Neuroeconomic Theory”?

  3. Some topics of interests for neuroscientists • Information processing • Resource allocation • Competition and control • Monitoring • Self-management • Discounting • Preferential access to information, etc. • Remarkably similar to the topics of research on the • “theory of the firm”

  4. Objective of this research • Understand behaviors difficult to reconcile with traditional • theories (just as recent behavioral economics literature): • Guilt • Self-imposed rules • Mistaken consumption, etc. • Provide “micro-microfoundations” for characteristics • traditionally considered exogenous: • Discounting • Risk-aversion, etc. • Open the black-box of decision-making just as the modern theory of the firm opened the black-box of the firm • Revisit the individual decision-making paradigm • (not decision-theory but game-theory approach)

  5. This paper Incorporate in a model of the brain two findings that have received support in neuro-experiments : • Conflict in the brain between • Forward-looking system (cortical system)capable of intertemporal tradeoffs • Myopic system (limbic system)interested only in immediate gratification [McClure et al. (2004)] • Restricted cognitive access within brain to information [Berns et al. (1997), Whalen et al. (1998)] “The heart has its reasons which reason knows nothing of” (Blaise Pascal)

  6. An important caveat • Assumptions based on neuroscience evidence: • Conflict between myopic and forward-looking • Asymmetric information • Hierarchical order and control • Modeling choices for which there is no evidence for or against (yet!): • Vertical hierarchy between • Forward-looking = “planner” • Myopic = “doer” • Private information possessed by myopic

  7. Related literature • Hyperbolic discounting with incomplete information(Carrillo-Mariotti, Brocas-Carrillo, Benabou-Tirole, Amador-Werning-Angeletos) Main Differences: • Conflict within (rather than between) periods • Asym. info within (rather than between) periods • Other dual-self theories (Thaler-Shefrin, Fudenberg-Levine, Loewenstein-O’Donoghue, Benhabib-Bisin, Bernheim-Rangel) Main Differences: • Asym. Info (rather than full info.) within periods • Constraints (rather than costs) in decision-making • (Two linked activities)

  8. The model 2 periods of consumption and labor and Utility “Principal” Pcortical system “Agent 1” A1 limbic system at date 1 “Agent 2” A2 limbic system at date 2 where u’ > 0, u” < 0 and θt is valuation at date t

  9. Consumption is non-negative: Labor is non-negative and bounded: 1 unit of labor  1 unit of income  1 unit of consumption Perfect capital markets with interest rate r > 0 Intertemporal budget constraint: [Note: no individual rationality constraint]

  10. Atchooses his preferred pair … but P can restrain At’s choices, and we allow any conceivable rule / restriction such as: • “consumption cannot exceed labor” • “labor must be at least x ” • “utility must be the same for both agents”, etc. • P deals with A1and A2sequentially Principal P date 1 date 2 t Agent 1 A1 Agent 2 A2

  11. For each θt , P imposes on Ata specific pair : Benchmark: conflict under full information P knows the valuation θt of At , so P solves:

  12. Consumption at t increases with θt (valuation at t ) • Labor at 1 is maximum (positive interest rate on savings) • Labor at 2 is adjusted to meet budget constraint • Positive relation consumption at 1+2 and labor at 1+2“work more in your lifetime to consume more in your lifetime”(due to intertemporal budget constraint) • No relation between consumption at 1 and labor at 1

  13. Conflict under asymmetric information At knows his valuation θt P only knows that θt i.i.d. F(θt)  P cannot impose restrictions that depend on valuation θt Note: Because constraint (no access to θt ) rather than exogenous cost of imposing choices (e.g. c(θt - θt’) when θt ≠ θt’ ): • No presupposed tradeoff • No preconceived idea of which restriction P willimpose

  14. Trivial. No restrictions (except budget balance) because at date 2 no conflict between P and A2 Optimal rule at date 2: P vs. A2 sunk Principal P date 2 t Agent 2 A2 A2 chooses

  15. Optimal rule at date 1: P vs. A1 Principal P date 1 t Agent 1 A1

  16. P offers the following menu of consumption and labor pairs : • A1 picks the pair he prefers • Note that the pairs are designed such that • Different valuations  different choices • Higher valuation  more consumption and more labor [the result is reminiscent of the mechanism design literature]

  17. Some conclusions • Endogenous emergence of (second-best) self-imposed rule:“work more today if you want to consume more today”. • Behavior has “a feeling of guilt” without assuming it. • Current reward (leisure) tracks current earning (one-day-at-a-time, narrow bracketing effect). • No consumption smoothing, with testable implications.Distribution of consumption over life cycle depends on: • Source of income (endowment vs. current labor) • Period-to-period access to labor

  18. Asym. info. vs. Full info. “similar to” Positive discounting vs. No discounting Time-preference rates • Consumption shifts to first period • Labor shifts to second period • Increase in consumption greater for high valuations • Decrease in labor greater for low valuations

  19. But there are also differences: distribution F(θt) from which valuations are drawn affects consumption. Some conclusions • “Micro-microfoundations” for intertemporal discounting. • Testable (?) differences: given current valuation, consumption is smaller if individual usually likes the good a lot.

  20. “Incentive salience” and “visceral factors” Neuroscience: “incentive salience” [Berridge, 2003] • One system mediates motivation to seek pleasure (wanting) • A different system mediates the feeling of pleasure (liking) Stimulus of 1st system  more work for same reward Social Psychology: “visceral factors” [Loewenstein, 1996]Emotions (fear, anger) and drives (hunger)  discrepancy optimal vs. realized (out-of-control) behavior

  21. “liking” Principal P date 1 date 2 t Agent 1 A1 Agent 2 A2 “wanting at 1” “wanting at 2” At is tempted to overconsume (biased motivation) P does not integrate At ’s salience

  22. Optimal rule at date 1: Pvs. A1very similar to previous case • P offers a menu of consumption and labor pairs • Higherθ1 higher c1 and higher n1

  23. P imposes only two constraints: Consumption cap Budget balance A2 chooses: If θ2 < θ* : unconstrained optimal pair given his bias If θ2 > θ* : same pair as an agent with valuation θ* Optimal rule at date 2: P vs.A2 sunk Principal P date 2 t Agent 2 A2

  24. Some conclusions • Optimality requires a simple, non-intrusive rule-of-thumb:“do what you want as long as you don’t abuse” • Stronger bias  tighter control Note 1: not aware of similar result in any mechanism design problem in which P can use two tools Note 2: nice reinterpretation as parent / offspring relation

  25. Intuition. Three ways to satisfy “incentive compatibility”: • Freedom: choose whatever pair you prefer • Pooling: everyone is offered the same pair • Self-selection: specific monotonic relation between c and n Standard mechanism design: 3 (or 3 and 2 if only 3 not feasible) Our problem: 1 is costly only for strong conflict 2 is inefficient 3 implies wasted resources (excessive work, bad also for P) Optimality  1 for low conflict and 2 for high conflict

  26. What’s next? • Test of behavioral implications • Period-to-period labor opportunities affect consumption • How much the good is usually liked affects consumption • More realistic and comprehensive models of the brain. For this, we need many more neuroeconomic experiments to guide theoretical models (and viceversa): • Is the hierarchy of the myopic vs. forward looking “vertical”? • Is the superior information possessed by the myopic system? • Are systems with restricted access to knowledge aware of their informational deficit? • Does the forward looking system discount the future? • When are salient incentives more likely to operate?

More Related