1 / 50

Does Behavioral Finance add to our understanding of financial markets? by Per Bjarte Solibakke

Does Behavioral Finance add to our understanding of financial markets? by Per Bjarte Solibakke. Overview. Behavioral Finance Building Blocks of Behavioral Finance Limits of Arbitrage Psychology Biases Behavioral Finance and Financial Markets Market Puzzles

dewei
Télécharger la présentation

Does Behavioral Finance add to our understanding of financial markets? by Per Bjarte Solibakke

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Does Behavioral Finance add to our understanding of financial markets? by Per Bjarte Solibakke

  2. Overview • Behavioral Finance • Building Blocks of Behavioral Finance • Limits of Arbitrage • Psychology Biases • Behavioral Finance and Financial Markets • Market Puzzles • Cross Section of Average Asset Returns • Individual Investor/Security analyst behavior • Corporate Finance and Management Decision behavior • Summaries and Conclusions

  3. Behavioral Finance (BF) Behavioral Finance (BF) argues that some financial phenomena can plausible be understood using models in which some agents are not fully rational. Hence, BF deals mostly with investor irrationality / bounded rationality / cognitive and decision biases. Those biases create market ineffiencies in the shape of mispricings.

  4. Behavioral Finance (BF) The traditional finance paradigm, the Efficient Market Hypothesis (EMH), use models in which agents are rational, implying that • Agents’ beliefs are correct. • Given these beliefs, agents make choices that are normative acceptable (SEU, Savage, 1964)  In broad terms, BF argues that some financial phenomena can be better understood using models in which some agents are not fully rational.

  5. Behavioral Finance (BF) Moreover, the efficient market hypothesis (EMH) appealingly simple, seems to show that its predictions are not fully confirmed by available data. Applying the EMH, basic facts are not easily understood in: 1. the aggregate stock market, 2. the cross section of average returns and 3. individual trading/security analyst behavior 4. classical corporate finance management decisions

  6. Behavioral Finance (BF) Specifically, BF analyses what happens when we relax one or both, of the two tenets that underlie the finance view of rationality • Failure to apply Bayes’ law properly • Agent hold correct belief but makes choices that are normative questionable (incompatible by SEU)

  7. Behavioral Finance (BF) Main Objection against BF (arbitrage argument): Even if some agents are irrational, rational agents will prevent them from influencing security prices for very long periods of time. Recently a series of theoretical papers show that irrationality can have a substantial and long-lived impact on security prices.  The literature on “limits of arbitrage” is the first of two building blocks of behavioral finance.

  8. Limits of Arbitrage EMH suggests ”no free lunch” and security prices equal ”fundamental value”. Thesuggestion requires: Deviation from fundamental value or simply mispricing, creates attractive investment opportunities and that Rational investors will immediately snap up the opportunity BF disputes the first argument due to risk!

  9. Limits of Arbitrage Sources of risk: Fundamental Risk  imperfect substitute security 2. Noise Trader Risk  mispricing worsen in the short run 3. Implementation Costs  difficult selling securities short 4. Model Risk  relying 100% on a model of fundamental value

  10. Limits of Arbitrage Evidence: The ”joint hypothesis problems” make it difficult to provide definite evidence of inefficiency. However, the following financial market phenomena are almost certain mispricing, and persistent ones: • Twin shares (Royal Dutch and Shell Transport) • ADR’s (New York price <> Home country price) • Index Inclusions (Yahoo increased by 24%) • Internet Carve-Outs (3Com 5% IPO of Palm Inc.)

  11. Arbitrage Risk (ex. US 1995-2000) S&P500 and NASDAQ indices seemed highly overvalued! Few dared to act on their hunch, due to • Fundamental risk No effective substitute security. Using Russel 2000 will make the position vulnerable to large stocks news. • Noise trader risk Noise traders may push them up still further in the short run. • Model Risk Is the index really mispriced?

  12. Scenario: Limited efficient Markets Price and Value tend to converge, but markets can still move far from reality (fundamental/intrinsic values) at times. Hence, the raise and evolvement of market anomalies and deviations seem to suggest a need for building behavioural models assuming specific form for irrationality. • This is the second building block in behavioral finance: • Psychology biases or • Investor irrationality /bounded rationality / cognitive and decision biases

  13. Psychology biases of particular interest Two main groups of biases are found in the behavioral finance literature: 1. Beliefs 2. Preferences

  14. Psychology biases • Beliefs • Overconfidence Poor calibrating, certain occurrences (80%) and impossible occurrences (20%). Aggressive Trading. • Optimism and Mood effects, Wishful Thinking • Representativeness Base Rate neglect and Sample size neglectPast performance indicator for future performance • Conservatism Base rate are over-emphasised relative to sampleevidence

  15. Psychology biases • Beliefs (cont.) • Confirmation Bias Insufficient attention is paid to new data • Anchoring Slow adjustment • Memory Biases More recent events and more salient events will weight more heavily and distort the estimate

  16. Psychology biases • Preferences • The vast majority of models of preference is represented by the expectation of a von Neumann-Morgenstern utility function (EU). • Unfortunately, EU theory is systematically violated when choosing among risky gambles. Several suggestions for improvements. Prospect theory may be the most promising for financial applications (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979, 1992)

  17. Prospect Theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; Tversky and Kahneman, 1992) • Allais Example “Fanning out” (1953) show inconsistence in expected utility theory! • Consider choosing between A1 and A2: • A1 Sure gain of $1,000,000 • $5,000,000 with probability 0.10 • A2 $1,000,000 with probability 0.89 • $0 with probability 0.01 • Now consider choosing between B1 and B2: • B1 $5,000,000 with probability 0.10 • $0 with probability 0.90 • B2 $1,000,000 with probability 0.11 • $0 with probability 0.89 • To be consistent with expected utility theory, A1 is preferred to A2, if and only if B2 is preferred to B1

  18. Prospect Theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; Tversky and Kahneman, 1992) • Individuals focus more on “prospects” –gains and losses- than on total wealth • Consider choosing between C1 and C2: • C1 Sure gain of $240,000 • C2 $1,000,000 with probability 0.25 • $0 with probability 0.75 • Risk aversion makes most individuals to gravitate toward the sure gain. • Now consider choosing between D1 and D2: • D1 Sure loss of $750,000 • D2 Loss $1,000,000 with probability 0.75 • $0 with probability 0.25 • Choosing D2, which most individuals would do, makes the utility function “abnormally” convex because of the “certain loss aversion effect”, showing risk preference.  Investors are reluctant to sell at loss.

  19. Prospect Theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; Tversky and Kahneman, 1992) • Non-linear probability transformation • People are more sensitivity to differences in probabilities at higher probability levels: • Consider choosing between E1 and E2: • E1 Sure gain of $3,000 • E2 Gain $4,000 with probability 0.8 • $0 with probability 0.2 • where E1 is preferred to E2, and consider choosing between F1 and F2: • F1 Gain $4,000 with probability 0.2 • $0 with probability 0.8 • F2 Gain $3,000 with probability 0.25 • $0 with probability 0.75 • where F1 is preferred to F2.  Violate EU theory. •  People place much more weight on certain outcomes than merely probable outcomes: the certainty effect.

  20. Prospect Theory (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; Tversky and Kahneman, 1992) Contribute to a higher understanding of: 1. Framing: the way a problem is posed for the decision manager 2. Mental accounting in prospect theory is accounted for by the fact that the reference point from which gains and losses are calculated can change over time 3. Narrow framing is the tendency to treat individual gambles separately from other portions of wealth. 4. Regret theory is a tendency for people to feel the pain of regret at having made errors, not putting such errors into a larger perspective.

  21. Ambiguity Aversion (Ellsberg, 1961) Probabilities are rarely objectively known. Savage (1964) developed a counterpart to EU known as SEU. Ellsberg (1961) shows a violation of SEU. Two urns, 1 and 2. Urn 2 contains a total of 100 balls, 50 red and 50 blue. Urn 1 also contains 100 balls, again a mix of red and blue, but the subject does not know the proportion of each. Subjects are then asked to choose one of following two gambles, each of which involves a possible payment of $10,000, depending on the colour of a ball drawn at random from the relevant urn g1 : a ball is drawn from Urn 1, $10.000 if red, $0 if blue g2 : a ball is drawn from Urn 2, $10.000 if red, $0 if blue Subjects are then asked to choose between following two gambles: h1 : a ball is drawn from Urn 1, $10.000 if blue, $0 if red h2 : a ball is drawn from Urn 2, $10.000 if blue, $0 if red Typically, g2 is preferred to g1 and h2 is chosen over h1. Inconsistent with SEU.

  22. Ambiguity Aversion (Ellsberg, 1961) People dislike subjective, or vague uncertainty more than they dislike objective uncertainty (see Camerer and Weber, 1992 for a review.)  “ambiguity aversion”. Ambiguity can be defined as a situation where information that could be known, is not. Possibly, strengthen where people feel their competence in assessing relevant probabilities is low (Heath and Tversky, 1991).

  23. Does BF add to our Understanding of Financial Markets? Disclaimer: Note that the conventional efficient market view is not abandoned. I could have, if it was the goal of this presentation, found very many cases/results that suggest that the markets are impressively efficient. Hence, This is a behavioral oriented presentation attempting to understand phenomena applying psychological biases in financial markets.

  24. BF: The Aggregate Stock Market • Three puzzles from the aggregate stock market: • The equity premium (Mehra & Prescott (1985)) • Volatility (Name:Campbell (2000)) • Predictability • The reference to as puzzles, is that they are hard to rationalize in a simple consumption based model.

  25. BF: The Equity Premium Puzzle The essence is that the 3.9% excess return for stocks cannot easily be explained by risk. i) Prospect Theory (Benartzi and Thaler, 1995) Suppose where  and  are the probability weighting function and the value function from prospect theory, respectively. Rf,tand Rt+1are gross returns on T-Bills and the stock market from t to t+1, respectively.  is the fraction of his financial wealth allocated to stocks. Additional Assumptions: Gains and Losses of prospect theory refer to changes in financial wealth and the relevant time interval is [t, t+1] for gains and losses. To make Rf and R equally attractive: From prospect theory portfolio evaluation: Once a year. More frequent evaluation  myopic loss aversion.

  26. BF: The Equity Premium Puzzle i) Prospect Theory (Barberis, Huang and Santos, 2001) Suppose preferences Investors get utility from consumption + the holding of risky assets (X). The utility is determined by where 2.25 is from Tversky and Kahneman (1992). They show that loss aversion can indeed provide a partial rationalization of the high Sharpe ratio on the aggregate stock market.

  27. BF: The Equity Premium Puzzle ii) Ambiguity Aversion When faced with an ambiguity, people entertain a range of possible probability distributions and act to maximize the minimum expected utility under any candidate distribution. Epstein and Wang (1994) showed how such a approach could be incorporated into a dynamic asset pricing model. Maenhout (1999) applies state equations and non-linear objective functions to the equity premium. However, to explain the whole 3,9% equity premium requires an unreasonable high concern about misspecifications.  Only a partial explanation for the equity premium.

  28. BF: The Volatility Puzzle (Schiller, 1981 and LeRoy and Porter, 1981) The essence is that the empirical volatility of the price-dividend ratio cannot easily be explained by variation in expected dividend growth rate. • i) Beliefs (changing forecasts of future cash flows) • Investors believe that the mean dividend growth rate is more variable than it is. • The version of Representativeness known as the law of small numbers. 2. Overconfidence about private information. Positive private information will push prices up too high relative to current dividend.

  29. BF: The Volatility Puzzle (Schiller, 1981 and LeRoy and Porter, 1981) i) Beliefs (cont.) 3. Investors extrapolate past returns too far into the future. Again representativeness known as the law of small numbers. 4. Investors confuse real and nominal quantities when forecasting future cash flows (Ritter and Warr, 2000) Incompetence

  30. BF: The Volatility Puzzle (Schiller, 1981 and LeRoy and Porter, 1981) • ii) Preferences • A straightforward extension of the model presented under the equity premium puzzle can explain the volatility puzzle • where zt is a state variable tracking past losses and gains. The stock market is pushed up assuming good cashflow news. This create a cushion of prior gains (z)  lower risk aversion.  Discounting at a lower rate push prices further relative to current dividends.

  31. BF: The Cross-section of Average Returns • Anomalies: • The size premium (Fama and French, 1992) • Long-term Reversals (DeBondt and Thaler, 1985) • The Predictive power of Scaled-price Ratios (Fama and French, 1992) • Momentum (Jegadeesh and Titman, 1993) • Event studies of (e.g. Baker and Wurgler, 2000) • Earnings announcements • Dividend Announcements and Omissions • Stock Repurchases • Secondary Offerings

  32. BF: The Cross-section of Average Returns - Anomalies • Belief Based Models • 1. The anomalies is the result of systematic errors of investors using public information (Barberis et al. (1998)) • Representativeness bias and the law of small numbers • Conservatism suggest that investors put too little weight on the latest piece of earnings news relative to their prior beliefs. The model generates post-earnings announcement drift, momentum, long-term reversal and cross-sectional forecasting power for scaled-price ratios.

  33. BF: The Cross-section of Average Returns - Anomalies • Belief Based Models (cont.) • 2. The anomalies is the result of systematic errors of investors using private information (Daniel et al. (1998)) • Overconfidence If private information is positive the investor will push prices too far relative to fundamentals. To generate momentum and post-earnings announcement effect, model is extended so that public information change the private information asymmetrically (self-attribution bias). Initial overconfidence is on average followed by even greater overconfidence, generating momentum.

  34. BF: The Cross-section of Average Returns - Anomalies • Belief Based Models (cont.) • Chopra et al. (1992) and La Porta et al. (1997) provide compelling evidence that supports the idea that investors make irrational forecasts of future cash flows.

  35. BF: The Cross-section of Average Returns - Anomalies • Belief Based Models (cont.) • 3. Momentum and reversals may also be positive feedback trading, when one group of investors buy more of an asset which has recently gone up in value. (e.g. model in De Long et al. (1990). • Extrapolative expectations based on past returns due to representativeness and to the law of small numbers. 4. Hong and Stein (1999) build a model where two boundedly rational groups of investors interacts (subset of available information).  Hong et al. (1999) present supportive evidence for the view of Hong and Stein: the momentum effect is high in small firms.

  36. BF: The Cross-section of Average Returns - Anomalies • ii) Belief Based Models with institutional frictions • A large class of investors, mutual funds, are not allowed to short stocks. Miller (1977) shows that short sales constraints explain why high price-earnings ratio stocks earn lower returns. Scherbina (2000) and Cheng et al. (2000) confirms. 2. The implications of short sales constraints and differences of opinion for higher order moments, lead to skewness (Hong and Seng (1999))

  37. BF: The Cross-section of Average Returns - Anomalies iii) Preferences Barbereis and Huang (2000) show that applying prospect theory, narrow framing and a dynamic model of loss aversion, individual stocks can generate evidence on long term reversals and on scaled-price ratios.

  38. BF: Closed-end Funds (CeF) Why doesn’t CeF trade at the price of Net Asset Value (NAV)? Lee et al. (1991) argue that some of the individual investors who are primary the primary owners are noise traders, exhibiting irrational swings in their expectations about future fund returns (noise traders). The view predicts that closed-end funds should comove strongly, which is confirmed by Lee et al. (1991). Noise trader risk must be systematic. Another group of assets primary owned by individuals are small stocks. Consistent with the noise trader risk being systematic, Lee et al. (1991) find strong positive correlation.

  39. BF: Co-movements / Cross-Correlations • Lee et al. (1991) assume a “habitat” view of comovement. •  Many investors choose to trade only subset of available assets. As these investors’ risk or sentiment changes, they alter exposure inducing a common factor in the returns. • Barberis and Scheifer (2000) argues categorizing as a co- movement factor • Many investors group stocks into categories, and then allocate funds across these various categories. An asset added to a category should therefore begin comovement with the category.

  40. BF: Investor Behaviour Particular success in: • Explaining how groups of investors behave and • What kinds of portfolios investors choose to hold and trading Growing Importance as: • Cost of entering the market has fallen dramatically

  41. BF: Investor Behaviour • Insufficient diversification • Investors diversify their portfolio holdings much less than recommended by normative models of portfolio choice. French and Poterba (1991) show that investor are domestically biased (>90%). Grinblatt and Keloharju (1999) show geographical local preferences in Finland.  Ambiguity and Familiarity offers a simple explanation; the degree of confidence in the probability distribution is important. • Naive diversification • Investors diversify applying the 1/n heuristic, whatever option that exist. •  Investor incompetence

  42. BF: Investor Behaviour • Excessive Trading • Overconfidence; investors believe they have information strong enough to justify a trade, while in fact it’s too weak. Moreover, Odean (1999) suggest a worse situation: Misinterpreted valid information. • Evidence: Barber and Odean (2000) • The Selling Decision • Disposition effect suggest that investors are reluctant to sell assets trading at a loss relative to purchase price. Odean (1998) show that investors are more willing to sell stocks that have gone up relative to buying price than down. 2. Prospect Theory and Narrow Framing 1. Irrational belief in mean reversion

  43. BF: Investor Behaviour • The Buying Decision • Odean (1999) shows that “Buys” are evenly split between prior winners and losers. Conditioning on the stock being a prior winner (loser) though, the stock is a big winner (loser). • - Attention effect • - Good past performance (momentum) • - Poor prior performance (undervalued and will rebound)

  44. BF: Security Analysts biases • Analysts forecasts and recommendations are biased • Stock recommendations are predominantly buys over sells, by a seven to one ratio (e.g. Womack (1996)) • Optimistic forecasts at 12-month and longer horizon (e.g. Brown 2001) • Analysts forecast errors are predictable based upon past accruals, past forecast revisions and other accounting value indicators. • Past accounting accruals predict forecast errors (Teoh and Wong (2001)) • Analysts seem to underreact to unfavorable information and overreact to favorable information (Easterwood and Nutt (1999))

  45. BF: Corporate Finance • 1. Security Issuance, Capital structure and Investment • Results from actions taken by rational managers faced with irrational investors. Market timing suggest: • security issuance and repurchase due to mis-pricing • Results from actions taken by managers that does not find mispricing irrational. Assuming Pecking-Order financing: • if stock prices go up, more attractive new projects eventually requiring new equity Baker and Wurgler (2000) find supportive evidence for the market timing hypothesis.

  46. BF: Corporate Finance • Why pay firms dividends? • Notion of self-control Consume the dividend but don’t the portfolio capital (Shefrin and Statman, 1984) • Mental Accounting Firms make it easier for investors to segregate gains from losses to increase their utility: Gains: Losses: • Avoiding Regret Stronger for action they took than action they failed to take

  47. BF: Corporate Finance • 3. Managerial Irrationality • Overconfidence i. Hubris Hypothesis (Roll, 1986) • ii. Future performance is positive: • Can explain pecking order financing • Correlation in Cash flow and investments • Free cash flow should be minimized

  48. Summaries and Conclusions • persuasive evidence that investors make major systematic errors • persuasive evidence that psychological biases affect market prices • indications that there is substantial misallocation of resources • However, much of the BF work is narrow and partial. As progress is made, more than one or two strands are incorporated into models.

  49. Summaries and Conclusions Two predictions for the understanding of financial markets: • We will find that most of our current theories, rational and behavioural, are wrong. • 2. There will be better theories.

  50. BF Fund in Operation Fund -- Objective The Fund aims to provide long term capital appreciation through investments in listed Japanese equities. The Fund's investments are based on insights from behavioural finance. In selecting companies for investment, the Fund will focus on stocks that are currently undervalued because of emotional and behavioural patterns present in stock markets. The selection of stocks is a systematic way. • Why Japan ? • Attractive valuation level: Nikkei 225 at its lowest in 15 years • Increased focus on shareholder value - beneficial for investors • Structural reforms heading in the right direction • Increased foreign investments in the Japanese equity market

More Related