1 / 31

Likelihood Methods in Ecology

This lecture explores hypothesis testing and statistical inference using likelihood methods in ecology. Topics include the philosophy of statistical inference, comparing alternate models, examples of hypothesis testing, and the issue of parsimony.

cmarty
Télécharger la présentation

Likelihood Methods in Ecology

An Image/Link below is provided (as is) to download presentation Download Policy: Content on the Website is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use and may not be sold / licensed / shared on other websites without getting consent from its author. Content is provided to you AS IS for your information and personal use only. Download presentation by click this link. While downloading, if for some reason you are not able to download a presentation, the publisher may have deleted the file from their server. During download, if you can't get a presentation, the file might be deleted by the publisher.

E N D

Presentation Transcript


  1. Likelihood Methods in Ecology Jan. 30 – Feb. 3, 2011 Rehovot, Israel Lecture 3Hypothesis Testing and Statistical Inference using Likelihood:The Central Role of Models

  2. Outline… • Statistical inference: • it’s what we use statistics for, but there are some surprisingly tricky philosophical difficulties that have plagued statisticians for over a century… • The “frequentist” vs. “likelihoodist” solutions • Hypothesis testing as a process of comparing alternate models • Examples – ANOVA and ANCOVA • The issue of parsimony

  3. Inference defined... “a: the act of passing from one proposition, statement, or judgment considered as true to another whose truth is believed to follow from that of the former b: the act of passing from statistical sample data to generalizations (as of the value of population parameters) usually with calculated degrees of certainty” Source: Merriam-Webster Online Dictionary

  4. Statistical Inference... ... Typically concerns inferring properties of an unknown distribution from data generated by that distribution ... Components: -- Point estimation -- Hypothesis testing -- Model comparison

  5. Probability and Inference • How do you choose the “correct inference” from your data, given inevitable uncertainty and error? • Can you assign a probability to your certainty in the correctness of a given inference? • (hint: if this is really important to you, then you should consider becoming a Bayesian, as long as you can accept what I consider to be some fairly objectionable baggage…) • How do you choose between alternate hypotheses? • Can you assess the strength of your evidence for alternate hypotheses?

  6. The crux of the problem... “Thus, our general problem is to assess the relative merits of rival hypotheses in the light of observational or experimental data that bear upon them....” (Edwards, pg 1). Edwards, A.W.F. 1992. Likelihood. Expanded Edition. Johns Hopkins University Press.

  7. Assigning Probabilities to Hypotheses • Unfortunately, hypotheses (or even different parameter estimates) can not generally be treated as “data” (outcomes of trials) • Statisticians have debated alternate solutions to this problem for centuries • (with no generally agreed upon solution)

  8. One Way Out: Classical “Frequentist” Statistics and Tests of Null Hypotheses • Probability is defined in terms of the outcome of a series of repeated trials.. • Hypothesis testing via “significance” of pre-defined “statistics” • What is the probability of observing a particular value of a predefined test statistic, given an assumed hypothesis about the underlying scientific model, and assumptions about the probability model of the test statistic... • Hypotheses are never “accepted”, but are “rejected” (categorically) if the probability of obtaining the observed value of the test statistic is very small (“p-value”)

  9. An Implicit Assumption • The data are an approximate “sample” of an underlying “true” reality – i.e., there is a true population mean, and the sample provides an estimate of it...

  10. Limitations of Frequentist Statistics • Do not provide a means of measuring relative strength of observational support for alternate hypotheses (merely helps decide when to “reject” individual hypotheses in comparison to a single “null” hypothesis...) • So you conclude the slope of the line is not = 0. How strong is your evidence that the slope is really 0.45 vs. 0.50? • Extremely non-intuitive: just what is a “confidence interval” anyway...

  11. Confidence Intervals A typical definition: “...If a series of samples are drawn and the mean of each calculated, 95% of the means would be expected to fall within the range of two* standard errors above and two below the mean of these means...” *actually, 1.96 Source: http://bmj.bmjjournals.com/collections/statsbk/4.shtml

  12. The “null hypothesis” approach • When and where is “strong inference” really useful? • When is it just an impediment to progress? Platt, J. R. 1964. Strong inference. Science 146:347-353 Stephens et al. 2005. Information theory and hypothesis testing: a call for pluralism. Journal of Applied Ecology 42:4-12.

  13. Chamberlain’s alternative: multiple working hypotheses • Science rarely progresses through a series of dichotomously branched decisions… • Instead, we are constantly trying to choose among a large set of alternate hypotheses • Concept is very old, but the computational power needed to adopt this approach has only recently become available… Chamberlain, T. C. 1890. The method of multiple working hypotheses. Science 15:92.

  14. Hypothesis testing and “significance” • Nester’s (1996) Creed: • TREATMENTS: all treatments differ • FACTORS: all factors interact • CORRELATIONS: all variables are correlated • POPULATIONS: no two populations are identical in any respect • NORMALITY: no data are normally distributed • VARIANCES: variances are never equal • MODELS: all models are wrong • EQUALITY: no two numbers are the same • SIZE: many numbers are very small Nester, M. R. 1996. An applied statistician’s creed. Applied Statistician 45:401-410

  15. Hypothesis testing vs. estimation “The problem of estimation is of more central importance, (than hypothesis testing)..for in almost all situations we know that the effect whose significance we are measuring is perfectly real, however small; what is at issue is its magnitude.” (Edwards, 1992, pg. 2) “An insignificant result, far from telling us that the effect is non-existent, merely warns us that the sample was not large enough to reveal it.” (Edwards, 1992, pg. 2)

  16. Hypothesis testing and probability: the likelihood compromise • Probability (of the data) can not generally be used directly to test alternate hypotheses (about parameters)...

  17. The “Likelihood Principle” In plain English: “The likelihood (L) of the set of parameters (θ) (in the scientific model), given an observation (x) is proportional to the probability of observing the data, given the parameters...” {and this probability is something we can calculate, using the appropriate underlying probability model (i.e. a PDF)}

  18. The most important point of the course… Any hypothesis test can be framed as a comparison of alternate models… (and being free of the constraints imposed by the alternate models embedded in classical statistical tests is perhaps the most important benefit of the likelihood approach…)

  19. A simple example:The likelihood alternative to 1-way ANOVA • Basic model: a set of observations (j=1..n) that can be classified into i = 1..a distinct groups (i.e. levels of treatment A) • A likelihood alternative

  20. Differences in Frequentist vs. Likelihood Approaches • Traditional Frequentist Approach: • Report “significance” of a test that …… based on a test statistic calculated from sums of squares (F statistic), with a necessary assumption of a homogeneous and normally distributed error • Likelihood Approach • Compare a set of alternate models, assess the strength of evidence in your data for each of them, and identify the “best” model • If the assumption about the error term isn’t appropriate, use a different error term!

  21. So, what would make sense as alternate models? Our first model A “null” model: Could and should you test additional models that lump some groups together (particularly if that lumping is based on looking at the estimated group means)?

  22. Remember that the error term is part of the model… And you don’t just have to accept that a simple, normally distributed, homogeneous error is appropriate… Estimate a separate error term for each group Or an error term that varies as a function of the predicted value Or where the error isn’t normally distributed

  23. A more general notation for the model… The “scientific model” And a likelihood function [ g(yi|θ) ]specifies the probability of observing yi, given the predicted value for that observation ( ) (i.e. calculated as a function of the parameters in the scientific model), and any parameters in the PDF (i.e. σ)

  24. Another Example: Analysis of Covariance • A traditional ANCOVA model (homogeneous slopes): • What is restrictive about this model? • How would you generalize this in a likelihood framework? • What alternate models are you testing with the standard frequentist statistics? • What more general alternate models might you like to test?

  25. But is likelihood enough? The challenge of parsimony The importance of seeking simple answers... “It will not be sufficient, when faced with a mass of observations, to plead special creation, even though, as we shall see, such a hypothesis commands a higher numerical likelihood than any other.” (Edwards, 1992, pg. 1, in explaining the need for a rigorous basis for scientific inference, given uncertainty in nature...)

  26. Models, Truth, and “Full Reality”(The Burnham and Anderson view...) “We believe that “truth” (full reality) in the biological sciences has essentially infinite dimension, and hence ... cannot be revealed with only ... finite data and a “model” of those data... ... We can only hope to identify a model that provides a good approximation to the data available.” (Burnham and Anderson 2002, pg. 20)

  27. The “full” model • What I irreverently call the “god” model: everything is the way it is because it is… • In statistical terms, this is simply a model with asmany parameters as observations • i.e.: xi = θi This will always be the model with the highest likelihood! (but it won’t be the most parsimonious)…

  28. Parsimony, Ockham’s razor, and drawing elephants... William of Ockham (1285-1349): “Pluralitas non est ponenda sine neccesitate” “entities should not be multiplied unnecessarily” “Parsimony: ... 2: economy in the use of means to an end; especially: economy of explanation in conformity with Occam's razor” (Merriam-Webster Online Dictionary)

  29. So how many parameters DOES it take to draw an elephant...?* Information Theory perspective: “How much information is lost when using a simple model to approximate reality?” Answer: the Kullback-Leibler Distance (generally unknowable) More Practical Answer: Akaike’s Information Criterion (AIC) identifies the model that minimizes KL distance *30 would “carry a chemical engineer into preliminary design” (Wel, 1975) (cited in B&A, pg 30)

  30. The brave new world… • Science is the development of simplified models as explanations (approximations) of reality… • The “quality” of the explanation (the model) will be a balance of many factors (both quantitative and qualitative)

  31. Consilience… E.O. Wilson’s view of science • In his book Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge (1998) , Wilson asserts that the sciences, humanities, and arts have a common goal: to give a purpose to understanding the details, to lend to all inquirers "a conviction, far deeper than a mere working proposition, that the world is orderly and can be explained by a small number of natural laws." Source: Wikipedia

More Related